Skip to main content

Full text of "An Historical Introduction To Modren Philosphy"

See other formats


AN HISTORICAL 
INTRODUCTION 
TO MODERN 
PHILOSOPHY 


)y Hugh MILLER 

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Ot LoS AflgcleS 


THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
/j>47 New York 




PREFACE 


T 

i.HIS BOOK IS INTENDED TO LEAD THE READER TO AN 
understanding of contemporary philosophy, allowing 
lim to pl£|^ his fti^.paurts in the intellectual life of tliK time. 

Recent 'i^’^afices in science and logic have effected a radical 
eorientation erf thc^ht, necessitating profound readjustments 
] 1 our concepTOiw v the individual, society, and nature. So 
. eep do these changes go that they seem to cut through the 
. ving tissue which binds the present to the past. We face ut>' 
recedented tasks, to the solution of which the past brings little 
r no help; yet the tasks are so urgent that only immediate 
ction, unhindered by time-consuming thought, seems to be of 
vail. To this pressure of urgent and unprecedented tasks comes 
he modem habit of mind, which assumes that problems arising 
rat of present conditions must and can be solved by a better 
terceprion of present activities. How should history help meet 
[^e emergency which history has precipitated? 
a; The publication of an historical introduction to philosophy 
i{jherefore calls for some defense. The full defense of this his- 
orical approach must be left to the chapters which follow. 
These chapters indicate the nature of the problem which has 
timulated the development of the western intellect, a problem 
/hich has become steadily more insistent, until today its solu- 
bn is in literal fact a matter of Ufe and death. The problem 



Vt 

^ strength of those very advances in science and logic which 
titially threw us into intellectual confusion, it is possible to 
neiem the moral foundation on which must be erected the 
ilojjpionwealth of man. 

T; is the task of philosophy to discern and to promulgate this 
Weal truth, making itself the center and container of all educa- 
'caL For of what profit is science, or art, or any industrial or 
Sessional technique, if there be none alive to put it to use? 
ys^e bibliographies appended to all but the later chapters are 
•uifcnt to be suggestive rather than exhaustive, directing the su*' 
■icfe to reading-matter which should be available in coll^ 

! (i public libraries. The concurrent reading of one or 
niirt histories of philosophy will amplify what is preseyi^ 
f i'book, and provide a basis for its critical estimate. E^v 
lisommended are the selections from the philosophy, ^ 
idves. It is by coming to grips with these men wh^ 
css shaped the human intellect that the student y 
lod develop his own intellectual power. These yj 
gt viewed critically, with understanding of the Q/i 
htrioned them. For it is still and always true th?f 


“Who reads . i 

Incessantly, and to his reading htmg y 
A spirit and judgment equal or supejZ 
Unsettled and uncertain still remaiv 
Deep versed in books but shallov ’ 


e 
r 

l; 

h 

' .^ay the ready spirit of Milton, w/' 
I tanslate itself into action, be wi# 

' his age, and who read this bool^ 

\ 

‘‘Oj Angeles 



TABLE OF CONTENTS 


THE PIACE OF PHILOSOPHY IN CONTEMPORARY LIFE 3 

I THE GREAT BEGINNINGS 

THE STRUGGLE FOR JUSTICE 
THE BIRTH OF SCIENCE*^ 

REFLECTION DEEPENS 

SOCRATES: THE WISEST AND BEST OF MEN 
PLATO: THE MASTER MIND 
THE SCIENCE OF ARISTOTLE 
HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 

n THE ANTECEDENTS OF MOr 
PHILOSOPHY 

A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 
THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 
THE BIRTH OF MODERN SOQETY 
THE RISE OF MODERN SCIENCE*^ 

THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY 0!f 
THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY/’ 

{continued) / 

THE EMPIRICAL 'PHILOSOPHr^ 

THE EMPIRICAl!; PHILOSOPff 

{continued) f. 

THE REVIVAL OF POLIT^'' 

KANT: CAN RATIONAE^ 

RECONCILED? / 

DIALECTICAL TSEJOlf 
/DIALECTICAL MATf 



AN HISTOR . lL INTRODUCTION 
TO MODERN PHILOSOPHY 



1 THE PLACE OF PHILOSOPHY 
IN CONTEMPORARY LIFE 


T 

JL HE RECENT WAR AND ITS AFTERMATH MAKE CLEAR 
to US the radical transition which has just occurred. 
Western Europe, the source of western civilization, is no longer 
its center. Western civilization has now two centers, one lo- 
cated in North America and the other in Russia. These two 
peoples head the van of human progress because they most 
explicitly base their social constitutions upon political theory. 
A political theory expounds some concept of justice. It there- 
fore involves initially an ethical or social philosophy, and 
finally a complete philosophy of nature and man. 

It is apparent to most of us that we are entering a new 
political epoch, an era in which government becomes to an un- 
precedented degree the agency by which man seeks to control 
his destiny, and especially to regulate conduct which directly 
aifects other human individuals. Government tends today to 
replace the religious, educational, charitable, and other institu- 
tions which earlier helped to ameliorate human relations. It is 
evident that this empowerment of government will proceed 
further, and that the United States and Soviet Russia loom so 
large in world affairs nbl only because of their size, but because 


3 



the place of philosophy in contemporary life 5 

achieved by establishing the right economic system. The con- 
troversy seems to turn on the question whether political his- 
tory determines economic history, or vice versa; and it is not 
perceived that the real issue is whether or not the individual 
shall possess political-economic power of any sort whatsoever. 
Very evidently, political history ib economically conditioned; 
but it is equally evident that at the same time the course of 
economic development is politically regulated. By focusing our 
attention upon the pseudo-problem of which sphere exclu- 
sively conditions the other, the absolutist deflects attention 
from the real problem, which is whether the individual should 
determine the political economy, i.e. the state, or be wholly 
determined by it. The question of liberty goes by default. 

Behind absolutistic doctrine, and supporting it, stands uni- 
versalistic or rationalistic philosophy, the most authoritative 
intellectual tradition of the past. Rationalism may be roughly 
defined as the view that all particular or individual character 
necessarily conforms to some definable system of natural law. 
Communism is pcriiaps the most thoroughgoing application to 
social and political life of this philosophy of natural law or 
universal necessity. Once we accept the premise of natural 
necessity, we are directly led to the conclusion that the human 
individual ncce.ssarily conforms to some pattern of social neces- 
sity, and that our aim should be the full realization of this 
pattern in the state or political economy. The state becomes 
identified with “universal being,” over which the individual 
has no control. 

■ What is the defense of the democrat against this rationalistic 
doctrine, which leaves to the human individual neither in- 
violable rights, nor political competence, nor in the last resort 
any intelligible status? The democrat must aflirm the absolute- 
ness of the individual, the ultimacy and the effectiveness of 
individual character. What socially transpires, he must say, is 
the end-result of a sum of individual actions, and not of any 
universal necessity; and he must affirm this to be true also of 



THE PLACE OF PHILOSOPHY IN CONTEMPORARY LIFE 7 

rights, no inherent value. Conduct becomes moral only as it 
conforms to civic law. This doctrine provides no rationale for 
democracy, which conceives the individual to be the creator 
of law and the master of the state. The doctrine of Hobbes has 
supported every sort of political absolutism, and has finally 
issued in the totalitarian state against which our wars were 
fought. It is the creed of political ‘absolutism. 

But today, even amongst ourselves, this absolutistic doctrine 
propagates itself in a new and powerful form. Is not govern- 
ment an agency of the people, is not law the instrument by 
which society imposes its will upon all.^ If so, should we not 
look behind government to those popular or social movements 
which arise by natural necessity, and which proceed by this 
same necessity to surmount or overturn every obstacle to their 
progress? Must not the individual either conform to this social 
necessity or be destroyed by it? And are not they who perceive 
this inevitable trend of social change, and who identify their 
effort with its direction, at once authorized and compelled to 
assume the powers of government and to become the agents 
of natural necessity? Is not their ability to seize and maintain 
government the proof of their right and duty to do so? This 
is the conception of natural necessity which today under- 
mines our faith in individual rights, and prepares the way for 
tyranny. 

How escape this conception? We should see that the concept 
of natural necessity is simply incompatible with democratic 
faith. According to this concept the individual person or thing 
only seems to act freely — ^in truth, every individual reaction is 
determined by some universal necessity. The individual reacts 
in his own character, but his individual character is only the 
local and transient manifestation of a universal form or natural 
law. Individual character only seems to be individual, in reality 
it is generic or universal. Here, in this depreciation of individual 
character as unreal or unimportant, and in this elevation of 
generic character as real and important, lies the premise of 



THE PLACE OF PHILOSOPHY IN CONTEMPORARY LIFE 9 

Must we, therefore, simply announce our preference for 
democratic government, saying that we just happen to like it 
better than totalitarian government; and should we affirm the 
postulate of individual freedom merely because it is logically 
compatible with democratic government, whereas the postulate 
of natural necessity is not? Is reason just a rationalization which 
malces explicit the implications of an irrational choice? No, 
we can elaborate the moral consequences or the ethical theories 
flowing from the two postulates. We may see that the very 
conception of value or goodness implies the power of the indi- 
vidual to make decisions and to acknowledge their effect upon 
his own and other lives. We may find that society is healthful 
only if the energies and intelligence of its individual members 
are morally and politically exercised. We may conclude that 
the democratic participation of each and every individual in 
government is the sole means of keeping government sensitive 
to the social pressures exerted upon it, so that all nondemocratic 
government is inherently unstable. These and other theoretical 
considerations may influence our choice of the postulate of 
freedom. 

But what if the postulate, however preferable on moral 
grounds, should be simply untrue? Is not human society part 
and parcel of the larger world? Did not man emerge as the 
inevitable result of an evolution of planetary life? Did not 
organic nature merely complicate certain physical processes 
which antedated the appearance of life? And is not physical 
nature wholly necessitated, wholly uniform in its obedience to 
physical laws? Can we suppose that freedom emerged with 
man, or perhaps with the amoeba? Must we not conclude that 
the appearance of freedom is an illusion, hiding frpm us the 
fact of physical necessity? 

It may jseem farfetched to make our faith in a certain form 
of government depend upon a general philosophy which in- 
quires into the character of everything that exists. Surely we 
are more cognizant of the nature and needs of man than we 



the place of philosophy in contemporary life II 

stringency in the requirement that particular fact ^l^.,^ey 
itself exactly and without residue to theoretical analysis. "Mfflgs 
must be completely subject to natural necessity, Jit seemed, 
since otherwise we could not discover this necessity worldng 
in particular occurrence, nor define it in theoretical formulas. 
The real character of things must be their uniformity or like- 
ness, and the apparent differences which individuate things 
must be illusory or meaningless. The human individual, a part 
of nature, cannot escape this necessity. Men, too, under their 
apparent individuality, must really be uniform and without 
essential difference. We are justified, therefore, in seeking the 
formulas which specifically define human character, and in 
imposing these formulas upon aU individuals; for just insofar 
as an individual departs from the formulas, he cannot be said 
to be really human. He becomes unnatural or monstrous — ^if 
he can be said to exist at all. 

In this way, by means, of the concept of natural necessity, 
modem science has been employed to support political and 
other absolutism, and to discredit liberal theory and practice. 
Science has increasingly become the real faith of modem man, 
steadily displacing all other faiths; and if our faith in science 
commits us to the tenets of political absolutism, there is little 
point in continuing our lip service to liberty. This is why all 
moral, philosophical, and political controver^ finally centers 
on a single issue: Upon which concept is science established, 
that of necessity or that of freedom? 

The thought of the past, we said, inclined to the conclusion 
that science involves the postulation of natural necessity. The 
modem intellect derives from ancient Greece, and the great 
thinkers of Greece who inaugurated this philosophical inquiry 
into the implications of natural science were able to do small 
justice to individuality and freedom. In its main current, which 
flows through Plato and Aristotle, philosophy attributed to 
existing things only a small measure of freedom. Things might 
depart from universal form, it was held, only at the price of 



■n OF PHILOSOPHY IN CONTEMPORARY LIFE 12 

TE PLACI J 

>f morality and justice, by turning to criticism of the 
ratio j^jjQgCic philosophy which affirms the postulate of neces- 
sity. criticism without positive construction soon degen- 
erated j^:o skepticism. It is not an accident that Hume, who 
first cl^i.rly saw the real issue and boldly questioned the dogma 
of natural necessity, is still known as a skeptic. It is not an 
accident that liberal and empirical philosophy has become in- 
creasingly confused, until today the very name of liberalism is 
in bad repute amdng intellectuals. Has the great tradition of 
liberty, which in the revolutions of the seventeenth and eight- 
eenth centuries moved to the establishment of free institutions, 
lost substance, aim, and momentum? Is liberalism really dis- 
credited? Must we conclude that democracy is only the transi- 
tion from monarchical tyranny to some other form of despot- 
ism? 

It almost began to seem so. But, fortunately for ourselves 
and for civilization, there have occurred withm this century 
certain revolutionary advances in the fields of logic and science, 
which turn the tables upon the authoritarian advocates of 
natural necessity, and which reestablish, we must believe con- 
clusively, the philosophical principle upon which is grounded 
all liberty of thought and practice: These recent advances show 
the belief in mathematical and physical necessity to be ground- 
less; and without the support of this basic necessity, the notions 
of chemical, biological, social, and other forms of necessity 
have little plausibility. We know today that not men alone, but 
all things, are free, even as Hume surmised. What looks like 
physical or other necessity is something else, the true identity 
of which awaits discovery. The postulate of natural necessity, 
we now perceive, was only a cover for ignorance of the causes 
of natural uniformity, and an excuse for not inquiring into 
these causes. Things are necessarily uniform, we said, and that 
is aU there is to it. We can no longer say this. Every uniformity 
or conformity of individuals consrimtes a specific scientific 



THE PLACE OF PHILOSOPHY IN CONTEMPORARY LIFE 1 5 

is. After three thousand years of philosophical effort we arrive 
at philosophical truth; and we find it to be the truth which 
was already realized in the long evolution to a liberal culture 
and a democratic society. Practice anticipated theory. 

It is to this philosophical truth, generative of a liberal and 
just civilization, that the student of philosophy is brought 
today. To convince oneself of its veracity, and to begin to 
grasp its intellectual and practical consequence, one must know 
something of the social and philosophical evolution leading 
up to its establishment. So studied, in the light of its issue in 
present truth, the history of western thought becomes much 
more than a chronology of thinkers, systems, and ideas. It 
resembles the dramatic history of some special science, each 
epochal stage of which is illuminated and made significant by 
the further advance to which it leads. The past is not Just the 
past. In this world where time can have no stop, the past is 
the movement which issues in the present; and only in the 
light of its present issue can the past be known. 

So we turn to an outline of the movement of western 
thought, disclosing the evolution of the human intellect. The 
-issue of this progress is truth; but the passion which motiv- 
ated the long progress was the passion for justice. That pas- 
sion, which created all the worlds, now creates the world to 
come. 


Notes for Fierther Reading 

This book presents philosophy as a smdy seeking to establish a 
broad intellectual foundation for political faith. There are other 
approaches to philosophy, for example from science, art, mathe- 
matics, religion. 

The prefaces or initial chapters of various histories of philos- 
ophy, and also the contents of various introductions to philosophy, 
may be used to study such varieties of approach. Several of these 
books will be found in any good college or city library, and the list 
below is intended to be suggestive only. Russell’s recently published 



I THE GREAT BEGINNINGS 



2 THE STRUGGLE FOR JUSTICE 


T i 3:1^ 

HE GREEKS OF ANTIQUITT ABE OUR. INTELLECTUAL 

pr ogenitors ; yet almost everything we look back to in 
Greek antiquity was the work of two short centuries, lying 
between 550 b.c. and 350 b.c., when Greek sculpture, architec- 
ture, drama, science, and philosophy reached their zenith . 
From that great and decisive begimiing proceeded the con- 
tinuous, remarkably self-conscious development which issues 
in the social and intellectual culture of today. Time and again, 
when men have lost their bearings, they have returned to that 
limpid stream of Greek life for guidance and assurance; and 
seldom have they come away unrefreshed. We may even do 
this still. Ancient Greece lives in us yet, in more ways than 
we know. StiU the Greek thinker stands, a guide-post pointing 
the way we have come and the way we must go. 

We have been taught, not least by the Greeks themselves, 
to think of the Greek truth as something timeless, suddenly 
appearing to hang forever like a great star in the firmament 
of the past. “There,” we say, ‘Svas Greece! ” as if we too be- 
lieved that Athena had sprung in all her cool maturity from 
the head of Zeus. But Greece also, of course, had its origins, its 
infancy and adolescence. Of this long growth we know littie. 
Suddenly the Greek genius found voice; and even as it sang, in 

19 



THE SIEUGGLE FOR JUSTICE 


21 


merchants of the inland sea. They kept alive their curious 
wonder at the strange customs of other peoples, a wonder 
which was to make them the observant analytical people they 
became and the creators of natural science. Above all they 
cherished their conception of what is right and proper in 
human government. They were fiercely individualistic, in the 
right sense of this word signifying a respect for individual 
being everywhere, a sentiment which is the contrary of mere 
egoism. This sense of the value of the human individual they 
translated into the political conviction that government should 
be by law. They believed that individuals may subject them- 
selves with dignity to a common law, but only with indignity 
to the fiat or whim of a personal ruler. 

Settled on sea-girt island and promontories, or in mountain- 
girt valleys and narrow littorals, the Greeks never became a 
nation. Their creation of governmental mechanisms was never 
so far developed as to show individual liberty to be compatible 
with large community. Only in the small sovereign city-state, 
they agreed, could a citizen actively participate in his govern- 
ment. So the fierce love of liberty became identified with a 
fierce loyalty to the city, precluding all larger. political unity; 
and upon this rock of isolationism the Greek people fotmdered. 

When the historical record begins, Greek society was 
already suffering from the consequences of this limitation. 
Gties economically favored by location had grown great; 
they had become wealthy in trade; and they had attracted in- 
creasing numbers of resident aliens who remained unfranchised, 
so that citizenship became an hereditary privilege and a segre- 
gative power. There appeared in such cities two factions whose 
political opposition reflected a radical divergence of economic 
interests. The landholders and farmers, citizens impoverished 
by a commerce which enriched all but them, were conservative 
or reactionary, resistant to change, doggedly jealous of their 
ancient rights and privileges, and convinced that they alone 
truly represented civic tradition and just law. They upheld the 



THE STRUGGLE FOR JUSTICE 


^3 

cultural unity. The cities now formed a loose confederation, 
at first under the direction of Sparta, whose militant way of 
life seemed to qualify it for this leadership; but it was the 
flexible genius of the Athenians, with their stout and clever 
sailors, which at Salamis in 480 b.c. secured definitive victory 
over great Persia. Athens was now commissioned by the con- 
federation to keep intact the naval power, since Persia still 
threatened. After a brief struggle against jealous Sparta, Athens 
assumed what was virtually a hegemony over the Greek cities, 
placing their contributions in its own treasury and seeking to 
bring cases of dispute to its civic courts. Sparta, militant and 
reactionary, was able to foment rebellion against progressive 
Athens on the ground, apparently justified, that Athens abused 
its commission and was aiming to subject all of Greece to its 
imperial self. 

The brilliant, unforgettable half century following the Per- 
sian War produced the architectural masterpieces, the deathless 
tragedies, the incomparable sculptures that still symbolize classi- 
cal Greece. Then, in the long, increasingly brutal, and ruinous 
Pelopoimesian War, which according to realistic Thucydides 
changed the very soul of Greece, that lyrical, gracious, ener- 
getic, and free spirit was darkened and all but destroyed. The 
cities which Persia could not conquer destroyed one another; 
and the Macedonian who waited in the north came down to 
subjugate them all, and turn the world barbarian again. 

One must not draw too close a parallel between the rise and 
fall of the Greek cities and the present ruin of Europe after a 
century rich in achievement. Yet it would be a worse error to 
recognize the forces which first stimulated and then destroyed 
Greece, and not to see these same forces working similar 
destruction in the modem world. The basic failure of Greece 
was its inability to advance to a just and stable political union, 
giving to all of the Greek cities a due share of political power 
and economic benefit. This failure in its turn was due in part 
to the imperialistic presumptions of Athens, and in part to the 



THE STRUGGLE FOR JUSTICE 


25 

gram in definitely moral and religions terms, and to distinguish 
their pursuit of liberty from license and laissez-faire. Their 
opponents, on the other hand, could point to an explicit ideal, 
redized in civic history and civic practice, and calling only for 
an obstinate fidelity. 

Thus the fall of Greece is a major demonstration of the im- 
portance of political,, moral, and religious forces in social evolu- 
tion. If Greek history had been merely an economic develop- 
ment, the Greek people would have been irresistibly drawn to 
political unity. It seems evident that the majority of Greek 
citizens were so impelled, their economic interests driving them 
that way. But the small groups whose economic interests were 
endangered by this movement were able to call into play very 
definite political and moral forces which worked against the 
economic trend. They were able to persuade the Greek people 
to sacrifice economic interest to patriotic pride, moral integrity, 
and religious piety. And they succeeded, in spite of the narrow- 
ness of their social ideal, in holding back the tide of progress. 

How could the progressives have undermined and overcome 
the resolute, uncompromising fundamentalism of their con- 
servative *opponents? Only by advancing to a larger political, 
moral, and religious vision, retaining what was strong, clean, 
honest, and true in the old faiths. The Athenians, for example, 
believed that their austere and beloved PaUas Athene was the 
daughter of Zeus, sprung from the very head and intelligence 
of that father of the gods. How could the Greek people be 
brought to worship Zeus himself, their common god, without 
these local intermediaries? How could they advance to a justice, 
a law, a morality and religion that was one and the same for all 
Greeks? This was the question to which the ancient Greek 
philosophers applied themselves; and out of their thought pro- 
ceeded Greek science and ethics. 

These men were not able to save Greece; but they began the 
movement which may save posterity. Their work falls into 
two distinct phases. The earlier thinkers had in mind primarily 



THE STRUGGLE FOR JUSTICE 


*7 

implied, as does some contemporary humanism, a repudiation, 
implicit or explicit, of the religious foundations of being. All 
Greek literature, all truly Greek science, is repeated warning 
against the thought that human life can be humanly lived in 
neglect of its religious sources, and that respect for man ex- 
cludes religious faith. Most intellectual of all the ancient peo- 
ples, the Greeks were also the most deeply religious. We can 
best understand this Greek outlook, at once humanistic and 
religious, by a study of the work of Aeschylus, greatest poet of 
the Greeks, in whose bold thought lies an insight common to 
all the great prophets of the past. 

Aeschylus, who fought at Marathon against the Persians in 
490 B.C., returned to Athens to create the Greek theater and 
to establish his own fame as one of the supreme dramatic poets 
of all time. Of his many dramas, most are lost; but we possess 
the gr^at trilogy portraying the death of Agamemnon and its 
fateful consequence. The story really begins earlier, when 
Agamemnon, king of Mycenae and leader of the fabulous ex- 
pedition against Troy, sacrifices his daughter Iphigenia to win 
a favorable wind for his fleet. His wife Clytemnestra does not 
forgive this ambitious violation of domestic love. She takes 
a lover, sets him on the throne beside her, orders the destruc- 
tion of Agamemnon’s son Orestes, and demeans his daughter 
Electra. When Agamemnon returns victorious after the ten- 
year siege of Troy, his wife murders him in the ceremonial bath. 
Orestes, saved from death, grows up in exile under the admon- 
ishments of the god Apollo to avenge his father. Come to man- 
hood, he returns secretly to Mycenae, and meets Electra at 
their father’s tomb. In the most moving and profound moment 
of the drama, these youngsters pledge themselves to their dread- 
ful task. Orestes slays his mother’s paramour, and then, on 
those same palace steps up which Agamemnon had gone to his 
doom, he lets quick death cut short his mother’s appeal to 
filial duty. Driven now by the Furies of remorse, Orestes 
wanders mad over Greece. Apollo leads him to Athens, and 



THE STRUGGLE FOR JUSTICE 2^ 

to divorce justice from righteousness, politics from religion. 
The laws of human society are not just if they are less merciful 
than the law of Zeus, giver of life. 

What Aeschylus said in great drama and high verse, Greek 
science repeated in sober but convincing prose. A century be- 
fore Aeschylus, great Anaximander had written that things- 
‘"return of necessity’’ to the chaos 'whence they had come as 
“punishment and reparation to one another for their injustice, 
according to the order of time.” This is still the law of tooth 
for tooth, of crime for crime; but Anaximander is already 
pointing in his cosmology to a larger law, which Socrates and 
Plato would show to transcend the earthly passage of crime 
and punishment. 

Notes for Further Reading 

A wealth of literature exists to illustrate the Greek milieu in 
which 'Science and philosophy developed. There is a dearth of 
studies,' however, relating the development of science and philos- 
ophy to the political achievement in which the Greek intellect had 
its &st exercise and expression. 

1. Murray, Gilbert, Five Stages of Greek Religion. New York, 

Columbia University Press, 1925. 

2. Aeschylzis, the Creator of Tragedy. Toronto, Oxford 

University Press, 1940. 

3. Aeschylus. The Tragedies of Aeschylus, trans. G. Murray and 

others. New York, The Macmillan Company, 1908. 

4. Cornford, F. M., From Religion to Philosophy. Boston, Long- 

mans, Green and Company, 1912. 

5. Barker, E., Greek Political Theory, 2nd ed. London, Methuen 

and Company, Ltd., 1925. 

6. Bury, J. B., “The Age of Illumination,’’ The Cambridge Ancient 

History. New York, The Macmillan Company, 1927, Vol. V. 

7. Sabine, G. H., A History of Political Theory. New York, 

Henry Holt and Company, 1937, Part I. 

8. Zimmern, A. E., The Greek Commonwealth. London and New 

York, Oxford University Press, 1922. 

9. Dickinson, G. L., The Geek View of Life. Garden City, Dou- 

bleday Doran and Company, 1925. 



THE BIRTH OF SCIENCE 


31 

and Egyptian industrial cities, its development cannot be ex- 
plained as an economic phenomenon. 

Science of a sort, we know, existed earlier and elsewhere. 
Thales of Miletus, the father of western science, is said to have 
learned his geometry in Egypt; and his prediction of the solar 
eclipse of 585 B.c. testifies to his access to astronomical records 
covering some centuries, accumulated perhaps in Mesopotamia, 
where astrologer-priests had long plotted the sky. But we 
ascribe the creation of science to Ionian Greece because it was 
there that the study of natural phenomena was undertaken, as 
we say, “for its own sake,” with an increasing recognition 
of the universal scope, the theoretical unity, and the distinctive 
method of science. Science arose, in short, as a philosophical 
enterprise which pursued nothing less than a comprehensive 
knowledge of the universe in its entirety. 

It i^ unfortunate that we have so little firsthand knowledge 
of theije great Ionian pioneers. Of their actual writings and say- 
ings we possess next to nothing, all our knowledge being hear- 
say. Our chief source is Aristotle, who included in his writings 
a short account of his more important predecessors; and 
Auristotle wrote not as an historian, but as a special pleader who 
wished to show how all earlier science pointed to his own con- 
ception of nature, or miserably failed where it did not. His ac- 
count of his predecessors is consequently somewhat misleading. 
Unfortunately this work of Aristotle was religiously accepted 
as an impartial record until very recently, and its misinterpreta- 
tion has colored every conception of Greek thought down to 
the present time. 

Aristotle believed that his own most important contribution 
to science was his doctrine of substance; and he accordingly 
interpreted each of his predecessors as presaging, more clearly 
or more dimly, his own view. Thus the history of Greek 
science became in his hands the account of a search for the 
underlying and universal substance which inheres in all things. 
But to understand the Ionian pioneers of science as merely 



THE BIRTH OB SCIENCE 33 

the aristocrapc Homeric pantheon some of the ancient local 
deities, indigjenous to Gireek soil and dear to the farmers for 
whom he wriote. But Hesiod too, even by his effort to revitalize 
the Olympian myth, betrayed his awareness of its inadequacy 
and assisted itai its obsequies. 

The Milesian progenitors of science boldly departed from 
this venerable but decadent mythology. They sought a new 
vehicle for the expression of their religious faith and for their 
perception 'of the religious unity md meaning of the world. 
Of this moral and religious motive, in them become realistic, 
was bom their science. They used their extended knowledge 
of fact, and their deep concern for the moral and political 
well-being of man, to create a new form of religion, so dif- 
ferent from other religious symbolisms that it has usually been 
contrasted with religion. Yet it was religion, because its motive 
was refigious. Let us examine for a few moments the thought 
of Thaues, Anaximander, and Anaximenes, citizens of Miletus, 
who initiated the development which was to become science 
and philosophy. 

Of Thales, who “flourished,” as the Greeks were wont to 
say, about 600 b.c., we know littie. A leader who vainly ap- 
pealed for a confederation of Greek cities to meet the menac- 
ing power of Persia, a navigator and astronomer, he evidently 
elaborated a cosmology the chief lines of which were retained 
by his Milesian and later successors. If, as reported, he said, 
“All things are full of gods,” he presurnably was proposing a 
realistic and empirical study of the forces inherent in things, 
since “gods” meant nothing less than “effective powers.” If he 
said, “The lodestone is alive, because it has the power to move 
iron,” he presumably pointed to a rather striking instance of 
this power inherent in all things. Thales proposed, in short, that 
we should recognize and acknowledge effective and forceful 
being wherever it appears, and not only on Mount Olympus, 
the home of the Homeric divinities. If he said, “All things are 
water,” he evidently had in mind a cosmic process in which 



jm Bmxnictf science 35 

||iealm o which everything articulate proceeds, and into 

; frbich it'’ again returns. 

But we need not be too much concerned with how Anaxi- 
mander developed his conception, nor even with what the con- 
cq>tion e:^actly was. More important is the sort of conception, 
the general approach and method, involved in this new specu- 
lation. .We'see here a sustained effort to conceive of nature as a 
angle, continuous, and self-regenerating process. We see, in 
short, the inauguration of mechanistic science. The mechanism 
of natural change, Anaximander taught, is always and every- 
wheie simply that of separation and commingling, i.e. of spatial 
displacement. Physical science has followed tlm direction of 
thought from that day to the present. 

Anaximander developed his mechanistic hypothesis on a 
grand scale, with superb genius. He conceived not only things, 
but worlds or “universes,” to generate and disappear again 
the fixad order of timer The initial separation of heavier from 
lighter 'elements, he thought, would generate a great vortex 
or whirlpool, with the moist earth at the center and the fiery 
sun at the periphery. The action of heat on moist earth would 
then generate living organisms, first simple but increasingly 
complex, man appearing as a late mutation from the fish. Un- 
fortunately this evolutionary conception was later submerged 
by a more static conception of nature, and not recovered until 
the close of our eighteenth century^ 

But most important and reveafing in Anaximander’s cos- 
mology, and as a rule least emphasized, is the teaching con- 
tained in the authentic fragment which we have quoted. 
^'‘Things pay a penalty and recompense to each other for their 
infusnee in the fixed order of time.” The conception of the 
change and movement of nature as only a spatial separation 
and commingling is a purely meclianistic conception; but this 
conception of spatial process is only one half of Anaximander’s 
science. It needs to be supplemented by an appreciation of 
“the fixed order of time,” i.e. the temporal dimension of fact; 



THE BIRTH OF SCaENCE 


37 

suggest that he really conceived of a single substance, appear- 
ing in four diflFerent degrees of denary. It must be remem- 
bered that these Milesian thinkers had no idea of empty space. 
They believed that the atmosphere extended indefinitely, until 
it reached the celestial firmament or “fire.” Nor did they dis- 
tinguish air from water vapor, the latter being for them only 
very moist air, and air oiily very dry vapor. So the clouds 
were “felted air,” according to Anaximenes. 

Aristotle says that Anaximenes made air the original ele- 
ment, the others being formed by its rarefaction or condensa- 
tion. There seems no reason why one element should be so 
distinguished, since the cycle of transmutation goes on eter- 
nally. But Anaximenes probably started with air, since for 
him it occupied most of space, in his description of the cyclical 
change. He may have further characterized air, since he said 
“/aw h our soul, being air, holds vs together, so do breath 
and at,- encompass the universe^ This statement informs us 
that these Milesian scientists did not distinguish organic from 
inorganic processes, as we do. They did not conceive of a 
physical world devoid of life and organic character. Yet apart 
from the above statement, we would call Anaximenes’ descrip- 
tion of nature a purely physical description. 

We have concerned ourselves here only with the largest 
conceptions of these Milesian thinkers. We know that they 
were active and productive scientists, pursuing special studies; 
and advancing special hypotheses in many fields. Thus Anax- 
imenes elaborated hypotheses on the origins of wind, rainbows, 
and earthquakes; he developed an astronomy according to 
which the heavens rotate like a cap or bowl about a disc-shaped 
earth, to produce the apparent rotation of the constellations 
about the pole-star. But we shall not refer to such special studies 
except where they involve a new direction of thought and a 
new approach or method in the prosecution of science. What 
distinguished these Milesian thinkers from earlier speculators 
was their combination of a realistic observation of matters of 



THE BIRTH OF SCIENCE 


39 

law. It was incumbent upon these Greeks, when their free 
institutions were menaced by external attack and internal crisis, 
to assure themselves of the righteousness and propriety to 
nature of these institutions; and they sought this assurance in 
a conception of nature which affirmed nature to be every- 
where governed by “natural law,” a conception which 
stretched Greek justice to the end of infinite space. 

Was this procedure, which has been justified by the con- 
tinuous development of the natural science it initiated, really 
less anthropomorphic than the earlier mythology? If the 
01)Tnpian pantheon saw in nature a feudal hierarchy of per- 
sonal divinities, did not tliis new cosmology extend to all of 
nature the pattern of human relations characteristic of the 
Greek city-state? We shall see that the concept of nature, 
even in/ its most objective and scientific elaboration, has never 
ceased jto be intimately related to the social and political habits 
of men. We shall find, indeed, that our conception of external 
nature 'so overlaps our conception of human nature that it is 
impossible to draw a sharp line dividing man from his natural 
environment, or to make our studies of man and of nature 
reciprocally exclusive. The studies of man and of nature have 
mutually and profitably conditioned each other. The percep- 
tion of human relations first quickened the perception of the 
coimections among things, and a better understanding of things 
then implemented our understanding of man. The word 
“anthropomorphic” is used to discredit any conception which 
interprets nature by analogy with human and social processes; 
but it is doubtful whether we can ever reach a concept of 
nature not open to this criticism. Such criticism is perhaps 
hypercriticism, in that it overlooks the continuity which re- 
lates man to his larger environment, “No art but nature makes 
that art,” said Shakespeare. 

This Milesian science initiated directions of thought which 
it could not follow very far, and raised theoretical problems 
which it did not clearly see. Its crucial problem was the rela- 



THE BIRTH OF SCIENCE 4^ 

surface of sixth and fifth century Greece. It was a period wluch 
saw many new forms of religious expression and organization, 
but these movements break through the surface of recorded 
history only here and there. They appear in some of the great 
tragedies, e.g. in the Bacchantes of Euripides, and in certain 
otherwise obscure developments of science and philosophy; 
and they must be called upon to explain the steady drift of 
Greek thought toward its issue in mystical Neoplatonism and 
Christianity. The movement was a popular one, constituting 
an appropriation of religious authority by the people at large, 
and suggestmg withdrawal from the established faiths which 
had become identified with certain political institutions and 
ruling groups. These “mystery-religions,” as we call them be- 
cause they usually centered in some purifying and redeeming 
sacrament, often claimed only to recover faiths immemorially 
old; but there is little doubt, whatever their historical origins, 
that th€^ constituted new developments of religious speculation 
appropriate to their age. An important shrine was at Eleusis, 
outside of Athens; and it is interesting to observe that official 
Athens tried to identify the Eleusinian mysteries with itself, as 
a means of influence over the Greek people. 

Pythagoras does not seem to have made any claim to an- 
tiquity for his cult, but seems rather to have presented it as 
a new revelation of truth. In the lodges which he founded, 
communities of men and women embraced a strict discipline 
of life and thought, accepting the authority of their tutors, 
and seeking to advance through well-defined stages of moral 
and intellectual illumination. In their self-government and self- 
discipline they resembled a medieval monastery, as they did 
also in their communistic economy. Less clear is the relation 
of the lodges to the society outside of them. For a time they 
exercised authority over the cities of southern Italy; 
came revolt, with Pythagoras forced into exile. Late*' 
gained power, but only to be destroyed by a perseoatics would 
dispersed their members and their beliefs over mu«lligible being, 



THE BIRTH OF SCIENCE 


43 

motive with religion, something we no longer find it easy to 
do. For Pythagoras the scientific pursuit of knowledge was a 
religious pursuit of truth, bringing emancipation to the soul. 
And still it is, if we would but know science in its wholeness 
again. 

Music served in this Pythagorean doctrine to bridge the dis- 
tance between moral and aesthetic art and descriptive science. 
The lilt and fall of melody, the thrill of harmony, depend on 
intervals of pitch which in their turn are conditioned by the 
mathematical proportions of the instruments used — ^by the 
lengths of string in the lute, by the spaced holes of the flute. 
The form and substance of music is its proportion, its meas- 
ured pattern of tone. Similarly Greek architecture, sculpture, 
and verse were of the classical sort which looks to symmetry, 
proportion, and repeated measure. It was this classical art 
which Pythagoras pursued in his puritan discipline of the in- 
dividual life, in his disposition of the communal life of the 
lodge, and finally in his scientific exploration of earth and 
heaven. The essential form of every sort of being, he taught, 
is its mathematical form. Mathematics is the key to every secret 
of nature and of life. 

So, with the Pythagoreans, science became consciously and 
emphatically quantitative, mathematical, precise. Exact science 
was bom; and even imong the Pythagoreans this mathematical 
science, both pure and applied, advanced to most notable 
achievements. Nor may we believe that any spiritual hunger 
less acute, less intense, or less abstracted from the world than 
this Pythagorean quest of supreme deliverance would have 
sufficed to establish firmly, so that it should never again be 
lost, this so theoretical and “impractical” wisdom, this mathe- 
matical science which has revolutionized human practice, and 
which has made of our modem industrialized world a monu- 
ment to pure theory. 

From that day onward, the study of mathematics would 
foster the belief in a realm of ideal and purely intelligible being. 



THE BIRTH OF SCIENCE 


45 

what difficult to grasp. They conceived of every number as 
having a definite geometrical shape. For example, there were 
“square” and “oblong” numbers; and the number ten was 
conceived as a pyramid, made up of four levels containing 
respectively four, three, two, and one units. The unit of num- 
ber was conceived as a volume possessed of spatial size; and 
they accordingly did not sharply distinguish arithmetic from 
geometry. Indeed, they took all science to be essentially the 
science of numbers, since they supposed every distinct sort 
of thing, and even every distinct sort of natural occurrence, 
to have “its number,” to know which was to know the essential 
character or true form of the thing. Thus there was one num- 
ber which was the horse, another which was man, another 
which was marriage, and so forth. But we should expect these 
errors, to us whimsical, in the first groping but prescient sketch 
of what /Was to become the universal mathematical science of 
today. Wor were the Pythagorean scientists prevented by their 
quaint numerology from mighty achievements in arithmetic, 
geometry, and astronomy. The mathematics and astronomy 
with which modem science began was essentially their crea- 
tion. From the Milesians, and through these mathematical 
Pythagoreans, came the systematic study of nature of which 
modem science is the faithful development; and about this 
backbone of authentic theoretical science was incorporated all 
later thought. One can hardly overestimate, therefore, the in- 
fluence of Pythagoras upon the intellectual development of 
man. 

Scarcely less important was his influence upon human prac- 
tice. His communal ideal was developed by Plato, through 
whom, as well as more directly, it influenced all later political 
thought. This ideal was variously pursued in the monastic 
movements of later antiquity, in the ecclesiastical system of 
medieval Christianity, and in the orders of the Knights Templar 
and Rosicmcians, through which it came into Freemasonry 
and esifi»-^o the college fraternity, which still curiously pre- 



THE BIRTH OF SCIENCE 


47 


Notes for Fwther Reading 

Prior to this century, the historian chiefly depended for his 
knowledge of early Greek thought upon Aristotle’s account of his 
predecessors. Today he has at his disposal the ‘‘fragments” consist- 
ing of quotations and references to the earlier thinkers gathered 
from later writings. The task of reconstructing the thought of the 
philosopher from these fragments is a difiicult one, comparable with 
that of the zoologist who “reconstructs” an extinct animal on the 
evidence of a few fossils. The best introduction to this field of 
scholarship for the English reader is probably the writings of John 
Burnet. 

1. Bakewell, C. M., Source Book in Ancient Fhilosophy. New 

York, Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1907. 

2. Nahm, M. C., ed., Selections from Early Greek Philosophy. 

New York, F. S. Crofts and Company, 1934. 

3. Burnet, J., Greek Philosophy. New York, The Macmillan Com- 

pany, 1914, Vol. I. 

^ Early Greek Philosophy y 3rd ed. New York, The Mac- 

millan Company, 1920. 

5. McClure, M. T., Ttoe Early Philosophers of Greece. New York, 

Appleton-Century Company, 1935. 

6. Gomperz, Th., The Presocratics, Greek Thinker Sy trans. L. 

Magnus. London, J. Murray, 1905, Vol. I. 

7. Cherniss, H. F., Aristotle^ s Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy. 

London and New York, Oxford University Press, 1935- 

8. Zeller, Ed., Outlines of the History of Greek Philosophy y trans. 

L. R. Palmer. New York, Henry Holt and Company, 1931, 
Parti. 



REFLECTION DEEPENS 


49 

vast economy, things being subject to a universal law even as 
Greek citizens were willingly subject to their civic laws. All 
change, Anaximander taught, is the working in nature of uni- 
versal justice, which keeps things within their proper bounds 
of space and time, yet gives to each its due. This moral con- 
ception was given a more concrete and material expression in 
the notion of a world the constituents of which are in flux, 
always coming and going, yet which preserve in their totality 
a constant balance and design. Thus the measures of water 
which become air are balanced by measures of air which be- 
come water or fire, the quantitative distribution of nature re- 
maining unaltered. This notion is not easy to work out in detail. 
Anaximander, we saw, needed a sort of fourth dimension, the 
indefinite, in order to explain change. In his view there is no 
change except that by which things emerge from or vanish 
into this me<fium. Anaximenes had explained all change as rare- 
faction or condensation — ^but a rarefaction and condensation 
of what? Of some one of the four types of being, or of some 
underlying stuff with four recognizable densities? Is ice frozen 
water, or is water melted ice? Or are ice and water both phases 
of some underlying substance? And in the last case, what is 
this substance in distinction from its variable appearances? 
The Milesian science raised several problems of this sort, be- 
cause of the desire to see in nature, at one and the same time, 
both a process of change and a preservation o|.^mething ele- 
mental and changeless. 

Heraclitus of Ephesus, a city which lay to the south of 
Miletus on that same Ionian coast, early in the fifth century 
concerned himself with these problems; and the conclusion he 
reached makes him /the first consistently dynarmc thinker in 
history. It is neitl^ necessary nor possible, Heraclitus con- 
cluded, to conc^e of ultimate substance. If there is real and 
universal change in the world, and there evidently is, there can 
be no real ijNEstance; for by “substance” we mean just what 
does not ditfrxTe. What is conserved within change, Heraclitus 



REFLECTION DEEPENS 


51 

The full implications of dynamism, indeed, are scarcely clear 
today, as we shall discover in our concluding chapters. What 
does it imply when we make change the most basic and ir- 
reducible character of nature? Something we call A becomes 
something we call B. If A and B constitute our perspectives 
upon this change, A being our view as we look back to its be- 
ginnings, B our view as we look forward to its terminus, then 
the sole reality confronting us is the process AB. But now let 
us universalize this conception, and think of vast reality itself as 
a process which is known only in its forward sweep, AB! We 
reach a conception of evolution so radical that neither Darwin 
nor any other scientist has yet thought to embrace it, and so dis- 
turbing that no philosopher has yet steadily contemplated it! 

Heraclitus did not proceed so far along the trail he was the 
first to blaze. He still subscribed to the Milesian cosmogony, 
which conceived the solid earth to be enclosed in permanent 
envelopes of water, air, and ethereal “fire.” To get back to this 
self-contained cosmos, he conceived aU changes to proceed 
reversibly, between two poles or opposites. “Fire lives the death 
of air, air lives the death of fire,” he said, meaning that there 
is in nature a downward and an upward movement, a reversible 
process, which we call “fire” in its upper limits and “air” in 
certain lower stages. Heraclitus also said, much as did Anaxi- 
mander, “Mortals are immortals, the one living the others 
death and dying the others life” This would seem to imply 
the immortality of a nonsubstantial soul, our birth and growth 
being our gradual transference from some other shadowy 
realm; and similarly our aging and death would restore sub- 
stance to something in that other realm. 

Heraclitus’ controlling purpose, we must believe, was to save 
and give force to the conception of universal justice which 
Anaximander had magnificently affirmed. According to Anax- 
imenes, all change is the condensation or rarefaction of some- 
thing indestructible; and this would mean that all change is 
merely the redisposition in space of this indestructible matter. 
But a science which reduces all change to material displace- 



REFLECTION DEEPENS 


53 

than outweighed by an intense and, in terms of his own doc- 
trine, literally burning faith in the intellectual power of man. 
All being, he taught, is some sort of flame; and in man this 
flame bums brightest in the intelligence. We know, he said, 
three stages of being. There is sleep, there is ordinary waldng, 
and there is the completely awakened life of intelligence, which 
has to ordinary experience the relation this latter has to the 
fitful dream-life of sleep. *^All things tue see 'when cnoake are 
death, even as those 'we see in slumber are sleep ... It is not 
meet to act and speak like men asleep.” In its full wakefulness, 
the spirit of man knows the cosmos and its divine tension. But 
man seems to fear this dry, flamelike life of intelligence. He 
prefers even to quench the flame in liquor, and to “go tripping, 
having his soul moist.” The call to intelligence is also a call to 
moral living. In dream, each man enters an idiosyncratic world 
private to himself, woven of his personal memories and desires; 
in ordinary waking, he shares a common perceptual world 
with his fellows; only in the elevated life of thought does he 
fully enter into “‘what is common” “The 7nany live as if they 
had each an understanding of his ovm . . . Those 'who speak 
'with understanding must hold fast to 'what is common as a 
city holds fast to its law, and even more strongly; for dl 
human laws are fed by the one divine law . . . Wisdom is 
one thing, it is to know the thought by which all things are 
steered through all things.” 

Heraclitus established no school, perhaps because his con- 
ception outranged the accustomed limits of the Greek mind; 
but his thought had broad influence upon all the later intel- 
lectual development. His most important contribution, the con- 
cept of an intelligible form which is the measure of change, 
and which is itself nonsubstantial, was recovered and fir mly 
established by Plato. 

'Parmenides of Elea, living, it is believed, a generation later 
than Heraclitus, until about the middle of the fifth century, 



KEFtECTION DEEPENS 


55 

were committed to the view that nature is discontinuous, since 
they understood all things to be numbers made up of discrete 
units possessed of volume. The Eleatic foEowers of Parmenides 
elaborated arguments which reduced this view to self-contra- 
diction and absurdity. Whether or not the Eleatic system 
originated in these mathematical problems, it certainly carried 
to its extreme conclusions the opposite view, which denies the 
discrete or discontinuous character of nature. The Eleatics be- 
lieved that nature is truly one, solid, infinite, without vacuum, 
without diversity, without change, without motion. Any other 
conception of nature, they taught, ulimately leads to the af- 
firmation of discontinuity, with all its consequent absurdities. 

The writings of Parmenides, taken by themselves, would 
suggest another origin of this Eleatic philosophy. “Whxt is,” 
goes the refrain of his poem, “is identical ndth ‘what can be 
thought.” “The 'way of truth” in short, is the way of the 
intellect; and “the 'way of opinion,” i.e. of error, is that which 
puts its trust in the senses. The evidence of the senses and the 
evidence of reason conflict; we must choose between the senses 
and reason; the senses lead us to self-contradiction, reason gives 
us coherent knowledge; so we must resolutely reject sense- 
evidence, and cleave only to reason. The Eleatics dismissed, as 
a realm wholly made up of illusions, the world which appears 
to us in ordinary perception. So Parmenides may have been 
only too loyal to the most essential doctrine of the otherworldly 
Pythagoras. It is not easy, in our empirical and naturalistic age, 
to sympathize with tliis sheer, uncompromising Eleatic ration- 
alism — only an occasional thinker subscribes to its logic today. 
But we should appreciate its service to the development 
of science and thought. In the fifth century b.c., it must be 
remembered, science was stiU struggling to establish itself as 
a method of inquiry reaching authentic natural knowledge; 
and it was becoming evident that science reaches conclusions 
far removed from those of cmrent opinion, and sometimes 
rather directly contrary to common sense. Would men accept 



REFLECTION DEEPENS 


57 

may and must be incorporated into some self-consistent theory. 
The other, which is really only the first differently stated, says 
that a theory is acceptable oidy where it violates none of the 
known facts. But what is “self-consistent theory”.!* Logic is 
the large answer to this question. And by what right does the 
theoretical scientist require the facts of nature to fit into some 
theory? Why should they not refuse to conform to any and 
every theory? Philosophy is the long answer to this question- 
It is no wonder that Plato, the greatest intellect of antiquity, 
esteemed Parmenides the most among all his predecessors; for 
Parmenides was the first thinker clearly to perceive the four fol- 
lowing facts: one, man always and necessarily brings certain 
presuppositions to his perception and understanding of nature; 
two, these presuppositions are somehow included in all his 
description of nature; three, these presuppositions constitute 
a purely rational, nonempirical or nonobservable factor in ail 
natural knowledge; four, these presuppositions point to some 
peculiar and profound relationship between nature and the 
mind of man. 

What can be, said Parmenides, is what can be thought. And 
what can be thought? Thought, said the Greek, is theoretical 
science, reaching a theory which defines, we may believe, the 
real, permanent, and universal character of nature. In appear- 
ance nature is diverse, variable, shifting, particular, chaotic. 
To theoretical study, however, nature is one, same, constant, 
tmiversal, perfectly formed. Which shall we believe, the senses 
or the intellect? If you are going to think at all, said Par- 
menides, think consistently and believe in your thought! Be- 
lieve that nature is in truth that one, same, inflexible, and whole 
Being which your theory describes! This conclusion, which 
identifies thought with theoretical knowledge, which prefers 
reason to the senses, which attributes “real being” only to uni- 
versal character and which dismisses particular and transient 
character as sense-illusion, we properly call rationalism. Par- 
menides inaugurated rationalistic philosophy. In so doing, he 



REFLECTION DEEPENS 


59 

its Milesian and its Pythagorean forms; and it was especially 
directed against the dynamic conception of Heraclitus. The 
older science found defenders, however, in the atomists, who 
turned the edge of the Eleatic criticism by stoutly affirming 
what Parmenides had called inconceivable, the existence of 
empty space. 

A certain Leticippus, who journeyed from Miletus to Elea 
and later settled in Abdera in northern Greece, first clearly 
enunciated the principle of atomism. “What is not,’’ he said, is 
as real as “what is” There is empty space; and the positively 
characterized sort of Being required by Parmenides exists in the 
form of small atoms, indivisible and eternal as Parmenides sup- 
posed, but moving in the void. Of Leucippus and his teaching 
we know litde; but the doctrine was elaborated in much detail 
by his great disciple, Democritus of Abdera. 

Atomistic theory has been of great importance in modem 
science, because it can be applied with quantitative methods 
allowing mathematical calculation. To what degree the Greek 
atomism was mathematical we do not know; it did not estab- 
lish any mathematical tradition. It did presuppose, however, 
the reduction of all qualitative character to quantitative spatial 
differences. The atoms, Democritus taught, are all of the same 
stuff; but they differ in size and shape, which results in dif- 
ferences of motion. All the observable qualitative difference 
and change of nature, excepting of course the qualitative dif- 
ference between this atomic stuff and pure space, is due to the 
various dispositions of atoms in space. Some of the atoms have 
ja^ed edges and cohere firmly together; others are smooth, 
and flow freely as liquid or air. Smallest and smoothest of all, 
and therefore speediest and most penetrating, are the atoms of 
light, the movement of which Democritus identified with con- 
sciousness or intelligence. 

In this atomistic doctrine, Greek science approached as near 
as it was to come to the mechanistic science of today. It pos- 
tulated only “atoms and the void,” the atoms being endowed 



KEFLECTION DEEPENS 6 1 

today, is based upon false suppositions. Heavy atoms would 
not fall faster than light atoms, atoms would not “fall” at all 
in empty space. But there was one presupposition that entitles 
this Greek atomism to respect, and which made it the influen- 
tial and profitable conception it was to become in modem 
science. This was its demand for completeness of explanation. 
Everything in nature, it insisted, happens of necessity, with 
adequate cause. Each stage of nature is completely determined 
by the preceding stages, and completely determines the suc- 
ceeding stages. This insistence upon the complete and per- 
fectly intelligible determination of events by events outweighs 
all the errors of the Greek atomism. It was this rigorous re- 
quirement, suggested certainly in part by Greek atomism, 
which made modem science the rigorous and effective mode 
of analysis it is. The doctrine that there is no chance in nature 
has recently come into question; but. it was this doctrine that 
chiefly aided modem science in its advance beyond Greek and 
medieval science. We owe much to these men. 

There were two other forms of atomism, or at least ap- 
proaches to atomism, of sufficient importance to warrant men- 
tion here. Empedocles of Acragas in Sicily, a younger con- 
temporary of Parmenides, elaborated a system which supposed 
that four different kinds of being (the familiar earth, water, 
air, and fire of the Milesians) might be conceived to be eternal 
and indestmctible, yet to be finely divided into parts which 
move concurrently, without the supposition of empty space, 
much as the parts of water may be swilled in a bowl. All things 
would be explained, in this prototype of modern chemistry, as 
compositions of these four elements, atomically divided. Em- 
pedocles had discovered by experiment that air, which the 
ancients conceived to fiU the space between earth and the 
“fiery” heavens, is a material body; and this encouraged him 
to believe, in spite of Parmenides, that motion is not incom- 
patible with a solid or filled Being, and with the denial of a 
vacuum. Earth may move in air. He still required some source 



REFLECTION DEEPENS 


63 

indeed he holds it to be infinitely divisible, which was the 
logical alternative allowed by the Eleatic argument. This bold 
step allowed him, he believed, to save all the change and ap- 
parent diversity of nature from the destructive Eleatic criticism. 
The substantial being of the world, he agrees, cannot change; 
but this being may exist in infinite qualitative modes, in all sorts 
of mixtures of these modes, and in changing mixmres of them. 
Everything will contain some proportion of every mode; but it 
will appear to us as that mode of which it contains most. Thus a 
white object contains much white, but also a trace of every 
other color, even of black. Copper is mostly copper, but every- 
thing has in it a little copper, and copper has in it a little of 
everything. This seems to us a rather curious and scientifically 
useless theory. Its virtue, apparently, was that it allowed the 
scientist to trust his senses, while at the same time it admitted 
that there could be no change of substance, since Parmenides 
had shown such change to be inconceivable. Like Empedocles, 
Anaxagoras needed some agency, distinct from these immutable 
qualities of nature, to mix and unmix things. He postulated 
therefore Nous or intelligence, a nonsubstantial agency re- 
sponsible for all motion, and the true ruler of the world. Plato 
makes Socrates complain that Anaxagoras called Nous the con- 
troller of the world, but that when he treated of any actual 
occurrence he explained it mechanically, as a result merely of 
the push and pull of things. Perhaps we should understand 
Anaxagoras to have subscribed m general to the science of 
Anaximander, with some additions of his own which were in- 
tended to meet the Eleatic criticism. 

In truth, the Milesian science seemed to be self-contradic- 
tory. It supposed that the happenings of nature are at 
once the result of a cosmic purpose, and the necessary and 
intelligible result of the impingement of the parts of nature 
against or in each other. Since our own science also shows this 
apparent contradiction, we caimot be too rough with the 
Adilesians and their apologists. Science, we shall fed, does not 



REFLECTION DEEPENS 


<55 

lowers failed to explain was the “illusion” of change. Change 
is real enough, it is a feature of the world. Plato, understanding 
Parmenides, would correct this failure. 

It may seem strange that in all antiquity there should have 
been only two or three men able to grasp this large but simple 
thought of Parmenides. But we shall find, as we proceed with 
t his study, that there have been only some half-dozen basic 
thoughts in all of this intellectual history — ^the bulk of philo- 
sophical speculation is the weaving of these few thoughts into 
new combinations and modes. 



SOCRATES: THE WISEST AND BEST OF ME ‘ 67 

restoring in new and powerful form the moral insight of free 
Greece, instead of showing that the just law of the city-state 
only administered the larger law of nature, the new science 
seemed to issue in something unintelligible and morally vacu- 
ous. During the second half of the fifth century there spread 
over the Greek world a blight of soplristry that was in part 
an enthusiastic but superficial absorption of the new science, 
in part an open or furtive rebellion which used the new science 
to discredit what was sober and sane in Greek life. Heraclitus 
was employed to justify a cheap subjectivism or relativism, 
making each individual his own truth and his own law. Par- 
menides was used as a model for clever logic-choppiag, which 
reduced every familiar or established truth to apparent ab- 
surdity. The atomistic science could be used to discredit every- 
thing but the crassest egoism. This sophistry and skepticism 
threatened the very existence of Greek society, and conse- 
quently it produced a strong reaction against science. Now that 
the old religion was no longer effective, only science remained 
to save Greek society. There had to arise, if science and society 
were to be saved, a man who could make clear the mord 
foundations of science. Such a man was Socrates. 

The sophistry and skepticism of the later fifth century would 
have not been so dangerous, if Greek society had not already 
been thrown into economic and political ferment. Their high 
optimism, which had carried the Greek cities to economic ex- 
pansion and to victory over Persia, became confused and reck- 
lless when the Greeks found themselves confronted with prob- 
lems of political and economic reconstruction, now acute and 
not to be postponed; and the forces which should have carried 
Greece to political unity were dissipated in civic conflict and 
abortive revolution. The sophists exploited these social and 
political tensions. They were usually clever but irresponsible 
men, often without fixed political or other ties, who traveled 
as teachers, publicists, and dispensers of the new learning from 
city to city, turning their little knowledge to pecuniary profit. 



SOCRATES: THE WISEST AND BEST OF MEN 


69 

Opinion — ^beyond opinion we cannot go. But whose opinion? 
That of the expert, surely. And who is the expert in this matter 
of the good life? Well, Protagoras suavely suggested, the ex- 
pert in this domain is the able and personable individual whose 
savoir-faire is his fortune; and for a goodly fee, Protagoras 
would transmit his own worldly wisdom to the children of 
his auditors. Protagoras with his eloquence and engaging per- 
sonality moved through the wealthier Greek cities, filling his 
lecture hall and his purse. 

Not a bad fellow, as Plato allows in his satire, was Protagoras. 
Blufily kind and shrewdly suave, he used a superficial skepti- 
cism to expound the truth that what a man can teach, in the 
last analysis, is only himself. But what is man — an opinion, or 
a truth? “Man is the measure of all things” can be a profound 
saying, as Socrates was to show. But in the mouth of Protagoras 
the phrase was something less than profound, since it ele- 
vated personal talent above a common truth and a common 
faith. 

Another sophist, the Sicilian Gorgias, also famous for his 
oratory, carried this relativism to its final implications in a 
skepticism virtually complete. If knowledge is only the opinion 
induced in us by temperament and environment, what basis of 
judgment among differing opinions can we find? Wliy is expert 
opinion best, or today’s opinion better than yesterday’s? The 
only criterion Gorgias could find was that of immediacy. We 
are certain of what we now immediately sense or feel. But 
Isuch sensation, stripped of all conceptual understanding, is in- 
communicable, ineffable. We can know the truth only if we 
do not speak it; to speak is necessarily to lie. 

Socrates was by many of his contemporaries, almost cer- 
tainly by those who encompassed his death, accounted just 
anodhier sophist. He resembled the sophists in his love of logical 
acrobatics, in his love and distrust of the new science, and in 
his demand that knowledge should have practical use. He 
differed from the sophists in his refusal to exploit intellectual 



SOCRATES: THE WISEST AND BEST OF MEN 7 1 

Athens and seeing it bent upon false courses, he devoted his 
life to arousing in others, especially in the Athenian youth who 
looked to him for entertainment and guidance, a moral fervor 
for the salvation of themselves and their city. In this work he 
neglected his private fortune, but found great satisfaction. 
Like his mother, who brought bodies to birth, he said, he was 
midwife to men’s thoughts. He wrote nothing because he be- 
teved that a disciple is a living book, much more effective 
than a written word that cannot answer back. 

What was his teaching? The soldier-author Xenophon gives 
us anecdotes about the man. Plato puts a whole philosophy 
into his mouth. Aristotle, whose biased reports of his predeces- 
sors usually misrepresent something factual, says that Socrates 
invented the method of definition; and this is a real clue. We 
know that Socrates was famous for his irony, that he was 
addicted to dialogue with short questions and answers, avoiding 
rhetoric, and that he identified virtue with understanding, vice 
with ignorance. When we study clues of this sort in the light 
of the philosophical development which he so powerftilly in- 
fluenced, we are led to certain broad conclusions concerning 
the Socratic teaching. 

His purpose, it is clear, was to carry to success the intention 
of the great pioneers of science, by showing how an inde- 
pendent and comprehensive study of nature does in fact reveal 
the moral foundation of being, which Greek society was apt 

i o call “justice.” The Milesian cosmology had failed in this 
Impose, because it developed into the mechanistic science of 
?he atomists, and supported the skeptical relativism of the 
sophists. Two errors, Socrates believed, were responsible for 
this failme. The first was an exaggerated interest in celestial 
natme, to the neglect of human affairs. The second was the 
failme, in part corrected by Parmenides, to realize the pre- 
suppositions or first principles of scientific study. It was this 
second error, Socrates saw, that led to relativism and skepticism. 
To correct these errors, it was necessary to discover the method 



SOCRATES: THE WISEST AND BEST OF MEN 73 

as all geometrical figures only specify what we call “geometri- 
cal form.” Geometrical theory, although it consists of defini- 
tions of specific forms, is tied up by these definitions into a 
unitary knowledge, which in its totality defines geometrical 
form; and the development of geometry presupposes an initial 
insight, which all geometrical science only makes explicit, into 
geometrical form as such. What, therefore, is the basic insight 
and the constitutive form of our knowledge of man? 

It is, Socrates concluded, the insight and the form which 
are justice, though perhaps it matters little what we call it. 
All the virtues — ^piety, modesty, courage, prudence, shrewd- 
ness, poise, etc. — arise from an understanding of the objective 
pattern of permanent and healthy human relationships within 
which we necessarily live. There are laws of human behavior, 
not in the modern sense which would explain every human 
act, however abnormal, as the instance of some law, but in the 
Greek sense which recognized certain permanent facts to 
respect which is to succeed and to violate which is to fail in 
all our doing. The basic virtue, consequently, is an insight into 
this universal norm of human behavior and social structure. 
There is a moral pattern which is proper to human life itself, 
and which can be departed from only with disaster to oneself 
and society. It is only in appearance that we can “get away 
with” violations of this moral law. Since the violation is of our 
ovm nature, as well as of social morality, it inevitably exacts its 
penalty. The sole wisdom is an understanding of this justice, 
'|he sole good is the doing of it. And really to know justice is 
automatically to do it, because we necessarily seek our own 
well-being. All wrongdoing is just confusion of mind or ig- 
norance. 

This teaching is so simple that it is easy to overlook its pro- 
fundity. To impart it, Socrates had to pursue and pin down 
with endless patience the ambiguities and evasions which arise 
in human discourse. To discover it, he had to plunge deeper 
into the mechanism of human thought than anyone before 



SOCXATES: THE WISEST AND BEST OF MEN 75 

descriptive science — ^we have no other science. In man, Socrates 
concluded, this universal norm becomes the norm of human 
behavior, a moral habit incorporated into good custom and 
true law. 

Socrates paid for this teaching with his life. Bom ten years 
after the final defeat of Persia, he saw Athens rise to power, 
rebuild itself in incomparable beauty, and make itself the bril- 
liant but hectic metropolis of that world. He loved Athens as 
he loved nothing else under God, not for its glory but for its 
stout courage and humaneness. He belonged to a group who 
were critical of the new imperialistic Athens; who believed that 
Pericles, compelled to depend increasingly upon chauvinistic 
and radical support for his liberal leadership, was leading 
Athens astray; who wished somehow to preserve the sober, 
homespun Athens of the past, even in building the new. Then 
Socrates and his friends saw these fears realized in the debacle 
and horror of the long war, and in the disraption of Athens 
between its “democratic” and “aristocratic” factions. When 
the reactionary faction revolted and seized power, Socrates 
incurred its anger by refusing to participate in its purge of 
innocent opponents. When the more democratic faction re- 
gained power, Socrates incurred its anger too by refusing, as 
officer for the day, to let the aristocratic generals who had lost 
a battle be made scapegoats for administrative inefficiency. So 
Socrates himself became the scapegoat. The most truly pious 
.of men was charged with impiety or blasphemy, the man who 
had devoted his life to restore in Athenian youth the old faith 
was charged with perverting youth. In vain the fathers and 
brothers of these youths spoke for Socrates. In a packed court 
and in one day he was indicted, tried, and condemned to 
death. 

Plato has given us an account of that trial. He did this in 
the Apology, in which surely only a scholarship become hyper- 
critical can see anything but verbatim report. Socrates, writes 
Plato, undertook his own defense, because his inner voice had 



SOCRATES: THE WISEST AND BEST OF MEN 77 

His intention was successful, but not in the way he hoped. 
When justice errs, the accused becomes judge and the court is 
the accused. The Greek people, learning that the most just of 
men had been destroyed in the name of justice, renounced 
their allegiance to the state and its law, and looked to another 
law, not mediated by man, for their salvation. They put law 
into the skies, and made God their judge. It is we later peoples 
who, after twenty centuries, reap the fruits of Socrates’ martyr- 
dom, by honoring again a human law that can, if man will, 
dispense the awful yet merciful justice that is God. 

We should spend more thought today upon the life, work, 
and death of this man; for time has brought our larger civil- 
ization through half its circle, to that selfsame place where 
stood in antique civilization the upright figure of Socrates. Our 
political, practical, and theoretical problems are almost identi- 
cally those which he and Greece encountered. We too have 
established a great society upon a political constitution. We 
have not yet, as did the Greeks, read that constitution into the 
larger univMse, to find in that universe, by scientific study, a 
larger Jaw. We have proceeded rather in the other direction. 
Having received from the Greeks their science, with its high 
vision df a universal and natural justice, we established our 
political constitution upon that faith, in the doctrine of in- 
alienable rights invested in the individual “by the laws of Nature 
and of Nature’s God.” But popular science has repeated in the 
modem period, only more slowly and relentlessly, the down- 
ward curve which it described in earlier antiquity. It has 
translated the natural law which is the divine justice of the 
world into a formula which is but the summary of what things 
do and are, a law which is obeyed in death as in life, in disease 
as in health, in crime as in community, in madness as in sanity. 
Once again, as in the later fifth century b.c., the foundations 
of the world are convulsed, and sophists thrive upon moral and 
intellectual confusion. Truth, we are told, is just someone’s 
opinion, the perspective upon fact of some economic or other 



SOCRATES: THE WISEST AND BEST OF MEN yp 

3. Gomperz, Th., Qreek Thinkers, txans. G. G. Berry. London, 

J. Murray, 1914. 

4. Zeller, Ed., Outlines of the History of Greek Philosophy. New 

York Henry Holt and Company, 1931, Part II, Chaps. I 
and IL ^ 

S' Taylor, A. E., Socrates. New York, Thomas Nelson and Sons, 
1939. 



PLATO; THE MASTERMIND 8 1 

word into the mouth of Socrates. Those who have assumed 
that Plato wished merely to exploit the fame of Socrates in 
order to advance his own doctrines forget that this fame was 
still infamy when the earlier dialogues of Plato were written; 
and one wonders a little at certain scholars who imply that 
the work of the greatest intellect of antiquity was bmlt upon 
a literary deceit. 

Although Plato was given to writing, he shared with Socrates 
a distrust of the written word. “One statement^'' he wrote 
when he was already old, “/ cm make in regard to all who 
have written or may write with a claim to knowledge of the 
subjects to which 1 devote myself. . . . Such writers cm, in 
my opinion, have no real acquaintance with the subject. 1 cer- 
tainly have composed no work in regard to it, nor shall I ever 
do so; for there is no way of putting it into words like other 
studies. Acquaintance with it must come rather after a long 
period of attendance or instruction in the subject itself and of 
close compmionship, when suddenly, like a blaze kindled by 
a leaping spark, it is generated in the soul and becomes self- 
sustaining.” Without pretending to knowledge of this esoteric 
teaching, we can learn the steps by which it was approached, 
since Plato tells us of these himself in his many dialogues. 

The most important of Plato’s writings for our knowledge of 
the man and his thought is the book-length dialogue The Re- 
public, in which he discourses of justice and presents his pic- 
ture of the good and healthy state; and the first importance of 
this work is its frank association of philosophical speculation 
with a practical political purpose. The primary purpose of 
Plato, and of the Academy which he founded, was political 
education; nor did Plato ever conceive of a science not in- 
spired and controlled by a political ideal. It is one and the same 
faith, he knew, which promotes the pursuit of justice and the 
pursuit of truth; and the Republic of Plato, perpetuating this 
faith which had created Greek science and for which Socrates 
had lived and died, has molded all subsequent history, by in- 



PLATO: THE MASTERMIND 


83 

fied in some way with the state and its institutions. They seek 
fame, honor, recognition; and their courage and dutifulness 
express this civic loyalty and ambition. This class Plato would 
house in a closed community, with no private property and 
without separate famiUes. It would undergo a rigorous physical 
tr aining and be liberally educated in the culture and ideals of 
its people. Its annual matings, scientifically managed to pro- 
duce an optimum progeny, would be ritualized so as to become 
a civic and religious sacrament; and the children from these 
unions would be fostered as wards of the state. Plato, astonish- 
ingly in that day, was a convinced feminist who would open 
every office to both sexes. The tliird class of citizens, so small 
as to constitute a council, would be obtained by selecting the 
best of the second class, and subjecting them to further scien- 
tific training and to trials in practical administrative work. 
T his council, self-perpetuated, would shape administrative 
policies and be the absolute rulers of the state. Plato would 
have the state remain small, not exceeding a few thousand 
citizens. He would keep it poor, in order not to incite envy, 
and warlike, in order to discourage aggressors. 

In this ideal and secure state, Plato says, we can at last dis- 
cover the seat of justice. Justice is the form or unitary pattern 
of this ideal society, in its proper balance of the three classes, 
a balance which secures the smooth fulfilment of the functions 
upon which society depends for its existence and health. 
\^ere the middle group is too strong, the state becomes a 
Sparta wholly geared for war. Where the bourgeoisie is too 
powerful, one gets an Athens or Corinth intent only upon 
economic ends and neglectful of the political needs of the 
state. But the well-balanced society will be a secure and truly 
prosperous polity. 

The democrat of today can scarcely take seriously this 
Platonic utopia, which would permanently locate the common 
responsibility of government in a self-perpetuating privileged 
class. To sympathize in any way with Plato’s conception we 



PLATO: THE MASTERMIND 


85 

whether it be the life of French peasants, of Middletown, of 
Washington or London “society,” or of a Czaiist nobility that 
has lost its honor. 

The next wider environment, which differs from the nar- 
rower more importantly in its structure than in its size, is that 
of politically organized society. Many men and women are of 
that soldierly and administrative type which spontaneously 
identifies itself with some large institution and is happy only 
in its service. These people are loyal, reliable, dutiful, but 
essentially stereotyped and unstatesmanlike, so that a people 
ruled by its bureaucrats is never well governed. They are reac- 
tionary because their whole response is to the actuality of the 
state or church or other visible institution. They serve the 
law in its letter, they revere the state in its de facto governors. 
They are the sticklers for privilege, for custom, for a morality 
that is uncritical of itself. 

But finally there are those who respond to a widest environ- 
ment, wider than society, embracing ^ humanity and whatever 
is more than that. This response to the largest environment is 
expressed in creative art, science, and religion — ^not, be it 
emphasized, in the stereotyped art, science, or religion which 
reveres the established forms of these interests more than the 
reality which they seek to embrace. All three interests are 
really a worship of truth, or of That Nameless which to know 
is truth — ^this is why Plato said that the knowledge he was 
concerned with could not be put in a book. These creative 
people are apt to be rather oblivious of political, economic, 
and domestic affairs; but it is their creative power alone, 
brought into our political economy, which lets us see society 
in its larger international context, so that we can observe its 
controlling conditions and its health or disease, and in the 
light of this dispassionate and disinterested vision steer it aright. 
Part of this vision, of course, is the perception of the structure 
of society itself, in its constituent elements of which Plato 
tries to tell us; but really to understand, to hold fast, and to 



PLATO: THE MASTERMIND 


87 

which we should aspire, the standard by which we must ap- 
praise existing conditions, and the guide to whatever justice 
we can achieve. We cannot aspire, appraise, or strive without 
a clear and intelligible ideal. 

This idealism is the key to Plato’s general philosophy. Look 
again at the psychology of the Repuhlicl The bourgeois citi- 
zen enjoys a good life only if the conditions of domestic and 
industrial economy are secured by stable government and just 
law. The soldier-administrator can pursue his ambition and 
have an object for his loyalty only in a firmly established and 
wisely governed state. The wise governor owes his wisdom 
to an intelligence of that universal law which his science dis- 
covers and his statesmanship applies. Universal law makes 
science possible, science makes the statesman possible, the 
statesman makes the state possible, the state and its order make 
industry and the family possible. The individual can function 
properly and hope to secure health and happiness only in an 
ordered community and an ordered world. In an imjust com- 
munity the just man must choose, as Socrates had to choose, 
between doing injustice and suffering disgrace and death. The 
good life is not merely an individual matter. It presupposes a 
good society and a good world. The nearer and the remoter 
environments both condition individual existence; and life can 
be lived intelligently only if the environment can be understood 
and its conditions met. Knowledge and a knowable world are 
presupposed by even the most individual human effort. Justice 
and law must rule the world — yet not rule it absolutely, because 
the individual must still be free to deal justly or unjustly, to 
act intelligently or blindly. The law of nature must be a per- 
suasive law, a norm which conditions prosperity and which 
ultimately conditions existence, but which does not imm ediately 
compel. 

This is Plato’s idealism. The law of nature, it says, is not 
just the summary of what goes on in nature. The law of 
nature is the law of health, of life, and of existence. (Much of 



PLATO: THE 2V1ASTERMIND 


89 

vast economy which is the cosmos. In the physical realm, 
certain constancies of setting- and rhythm provide the condi- 
tions of organic life; and animal and vegetable life reciprocally 
condition each other. Each natural species, indeed, is condi- 
tioned by many and perhaps by all other species, so that each 
species has its place, supporting and supported, within the uni- 
versal economy. All existence is a commerce or symbiosis. 
Simply by remaining true to its type and by perpetuating its 
type, each individual thing subscribes to the cosmic order. 
Fidelity to type is obedience to cosmic law. 

Man’s true law is his fidelity to man, i.e. to his human char- 
acter. Man is distinguished from the higher animals by his 
social nature — society is a form and condition of humane living. 
But man is even more basically differentiated from all other 
species by his intellectual faculties, arising from his sensitive- 
ness to the. largest environment about him, which is what 
makes human society possible. It is his scientific intellect that 
makes him moral; for it is through intellect alone that he per- 
ceives the universal plan, and learns that his integrity to human 
nature is his whole and sufficient health. To do evil is quite 
literally to die, since it is to become what one is not. And 
Socrates was therefore right when he equated righteousness 
vdth understanding and identified vice -with ignorance. 

In the cosmos, the law appears as the great conservator, 
perpetuating the species of physical and organic nature and 
holding them within their appropriate bounds and to their 
mutual service. But in the indi-vidual, the law appears as a 
creative force, since it is through the individual alone that the 
cosmic pattern is continually regenerated in existent nature. 
Plato’s most compelling paragraphs are his descriptions of the 
creative working of the law in ourselves. Even in its healthy 
appetite for good food, he might have said, the body seels 
its re-creative sustenance. In the passion of sex, he does say, 
it seeks its reproduction in the beautiful mate, with uncon- 
scious forethought for sound and healthy progeny. When ap- 



PLATO: THE MASTERMIND 


91 

having its source in the local and transient things which are the 
constituents of nature. At some risk we may call this concep- 
tion a dualism of Form and matter — ^this name at least is pref- 
erable to “The Theory of Ideas.” In the Tvmaeus, an important 
dialogue in which Plato is careful not to make use of Socrates, 
but advances his teaching merely as an hypothesis incapable of 
strict demonstration, a dualism of this sort is presented. The 
topic discussed is the creation of the world. The creative 
process of nature may be undeKtood, we are told, as the work- 
ing of a great demiitrge, a creative god immanent to the world. 
This divine artisan has at his disposal a material stuff, which is 
described somewhat atomistically. In incessant and chaotic mo- 
tion, and divided into small and inert particles, matter is ruled 
by mechanical necessity and is devoid of all large and intelli- 
gible design. Matter is in itself neither good nor bad, it is 
aesthetically and morally characterless or neutral. Matter is 
the “formless” not because it has no character whatsoever, 
but because its character is so local, shifting, and infinitely 
diversified that it cannot be steadily contemplated nor intelli- 
gibly defined. The creative demiurge has, however, a model 
accessible to his intelligent vision. This model is a transcendent 
Form, wholly beautiful, constant, and supremely intelligible. 
Gazing upon this Form, he shapes mechanical matter, so far as 
necessity allo’ws, into a material replica of the Form. What re- 
sults is the existent cosmos, compounded of Form and matter, of 
stability and motion, of sameness and difference, of universal in- 
telligible character and particular visible character, of beauty 
and defect, of success and failure, of goodness and decay, of 
truth and error. This divinity immanent to the world, Plato 
makes clear in other writings, indwells all things. It works in 
each thing as the response of that thing to the cosmic Form, 
and as a striving of that thing to be its true self, in fidelity to its 
type. In man, this response and this effort are enlarged to be- 
come a creative adoration of the cosmic Form. Man’s fidelity 
to type is his fidelity to his reason, which is his cognition of 



PLATO: THE MASTERMIND 93: 

which number itself devolves. But in accepting diis Eleatic 
insight, Plato did not renounce the Milesian science, which 
Heraclitus had shown to presuppose the radical and irreducible 
reality of change and motion. He accepted something also 
from the atomists, who had made clear the effectiveness of 
even the smallest and most particular constituents of nature 
in the determination first of their own destinies, and through 
these of the larger courses of nature. All of these apparently 
contradictory insights Plato recovered, reconciled, and con- 
served for posterity in that stupendous, simple, and in some 
respects irrefutable doctrine of Form and matter. At one 
stroke, leaning upon Socrates, Plato established again a theoret- 
ical science that was about to dissipate into paradox, sophistry, 
and skepticism. At one blow, Plato restored faith in the human 
intellect and its power to know truth, and propelled science 
up all the centuries to ourselves and the ages to come. And in 
restoring to man his intellectual faith, Plato restored to him 
also his moral faith, by showing that the world known to the 
intellect is a world compact of beauty and goodness, and con- 
tracted indissolubly with justice. After six centuries of modem 
criticism, criticism which in certain of its conclusions is alto- 
gether cogent, Plato looms larger today in human history than 
ever before; for criticism, finally, can only enlarge, not mini- 
mize, that Platonic truth. More than Plato man may hope to be; 
but to be less than Plato is degenerate. Such is the irreversibility 
of creative thought. 

It was necessary, of course, not only to devise this great 
conception compounding existent nature out of Form and 
matter, but to demonstrate its truth. The arguments used to 
do this were of two kinds. One of them applied the Socratic 
irony; it pretended to accept the skeptical or sophistical con- 
ceptions of those who denied truth or justice, and proceeded 
to show how even these conceptions illicitly assumed what 
they denied. Thus in the opening books of the Republic the 
sophist who insists that justice is only the legitimization by 



Plato: the mastermino 


95 

introduce them to mathematical science, i.e. to natural science. 

Mathematics is not, however, the end for Plato of our intel- 
lectual study. Just as we can break down the visible patterns 
of things into a few elementary geometrical figures, and then 
reduce our definitions of these to a number of axioms, so we 
can proceed upwards from this set of mathematical axioms to 
a still smaller number of metaphysical principles; and ulti- 
mately, Plato believed, one reaches an insight into that ineffable 
Being out of which all articulate and definable form proceeds. 
Into this dialectic, which was the culmination of Plato’s teach- 
ing, and which carries the thinker to a religious vision of the 
Good, we will not go, since it is that truth which Plato said 
could not be imparted by words. But it is evident that Plato 
found in mathematical science, with its rational certainty and 
its universal applicability, the great bastion of his mord and 
intellectual faith. 

In both of these arguments Plato leans to the rationalism of 
Parmenides, who first perceived clearly the theoretical form 
of science, and showed that it presupposes a unity of character 
in nature which is the object of science. But Plato combines 
the Eleatic insight with the insight of Heraclitus, and refuses 
to deny reality to motion, change, and diversity. These three 
thinkers, Heraclitus, Parmenides, and Plato, showed the limits 
within which aU theoretical speculation about nature and man 
must move. Change and. constancy, individual and universal 
character, motion and immobility must all be allowed reality. 

The Platonic metaphysics implies a Platonic theory of 
knowledge, or epistevwlogy. Plato’s epistemology is a modified 
rationalism, not the stark rationalism of Parmenides. Reason, 
he taught, is the faculty which discloses to us, within the 
transient actualities apprehended by the senses, the true forms 
of things. Between ordinary sensation and scientific intuition 
there are intermediate stages in common sense, ordinary under- 
standing, and artistic vision. Plato did not despise the senses. 
He made them a condition of all natural knowledge, providing 



PLATO: THE MASTERMIND 


97 

instances of general laws or specific processes, since this is the 
only way we can initially understand them. But why do in- 
dividuals so conform? What is our explanation of this deference 
of particular events to universal norms or general forms? 

Again and again in his writings Plato takes up this problem, 
only to let it fall again unsolved. There is no solution, he con- 
cludes, to this mystery upon which all theoretical knowledge 
and all intelligent conduct is established. Nor, we know after 
two thousand years of meditation upon this problem, is any 
solution possible so long as we identify knowledge, as did 
Plato, with a purely theoretical science or a purely theoretical 
philosophy. We can say with Plato that thmgs “participate” 
somehow in general forms; but how they do so, whether the 
general form molds the individual thing or the individual thing 
pursues the general form, we cannot say. Only ask this ques- 
tion and inquiry is balked, reason is stopped in its tracks. 

But this core of opaque unintelligibility at the very heart of 
the Platonic system has serious consequences. We do not get 
natural science simply out of mathematical axioms and their 
applications. To apply mathematics we must have prepared 
the way for it by an initial analysis of observable fact, in which 
we distinguish by means of qualitative differences certain 
types of things or processes. How can we be sure that the 
types we distinguish are the real forms, the authentic “species” 
of physical or organic nature? The Platonic rationalism pre- 
supposes, we see, a kind of foreknowledge of the “real” con- 
stitution of nature, prior to all experience of the individual 
constituents of nature and their behavior. This implication 
Plato duly recognized in his doctrine of reminiscence. Some- 
how, he suggested, we must bring with us, perhaps from an 
earlier existence, our infallible insight into the true forms of 
nature. Science is not a discovery, but only a rediscovery in 
particular situations of a cosmic structure the knowledge of 
which is given to us with intelligence itself. 

Thus Plato did Hot avoid, in the last resort, certain errors 



PLATO: THE MASTERMIND 


99 

tional mechanism of society, and which appears as a balance or 
proportion sustained amongst the parts of society. It is within 
this constitutional form that must proceed all of the life of 
society, if society is to remain healthy and not decay nor rup- 
ture. Further, this constitutional form appears on a larger scale 
as the constitution of the cosmos itself, in a functional mecha- 
nism which preserves the cosmic economy by stabilizing, “in 
the fixed order of time,” the species of nature and their recipro- 
cal dependence. This cosmic constitution is revealed to the 
human reason as a knowledge of universal Form, which allows 
man to pursue a theoretical science, discovering and defining 
that Form in its specific manifestations and its causal sequences. 
Finally, we found a crucial inadequacy in Plato’s thought, the 
consequence of which is an inescapable dogmatism. Plato’s 
error, we shall discover at the close of our review of modem 
philosophy, was to fail to distinguish the forms of society and 
science with sufficient rigor from the content which is condi- 
tioned by those forms. He did not distinguish the political con- 
ijl^tution from the changing body of custom and law; and he 
did not distinguish theoretical form from the changing content 
of specific hypothesis. He did not discover, in short, a cosmic 
law which hes beyond the specific processes of nature. But 
this is to anticipate. 

There was another Plato, whose aesthetic and religious in- 
sight always impelled, yet could never completely contain it- 
self within, the scientific studies of this supreme Greek intel- 
lect. This other Plato occasionally took the pen from the 
scientist’s fingers, and adjoined to the rigorous conceptual 
analysis a parable or myth, using artistic or religious symbolism 
to suggest a vision that intellect could approach but not com- 
municate. The myths of Plato may have preserved some of the 
imaginative conceptions used in the Pythagorean cult or in the 
mystery-religions. They treat of the immortality of the indi- 
vidual soul, of the day of judgment in which each individual 



PLATO: THE MASTERMIND 


lOI 


tant for its influence on medieval thought, and for its conception of 
the relation of eternal form to moving existence. 

The Republic, whether we attribute its teaching to Socrates or 
to Plato, remains the supreme Greek classic and the best introduc- 
tion to Plato himself. The Epistles, especially the seventh, shed ligjit 
on Plato’s political activity. 

1. The Dialogues of Plato, trans. B. Jowett. New York, Random 

House, Inc., 1937. 

2. Field, G. C., Plato md His Contemporaries. New York, E. P. 

Dutton and Company, Inc., 1930. 

3. Taylor, A. E., Plato. New York, Dial Press, Inc., 1936. 

4. Ritter, C. The Essence of Plato's Philosophy, trans. A. AUes. 

New York, Dial Press, Inc., 1933. 

5. Gomperz, Th., Greek Thinkers, trans. G. G. Berry. London, 

J. Murray, 1912, Vols. II, III. 

6. Zeller, Ed., Outlines of the History of Greek Philosophy, trans. 

L. R. Palmer, New York, Henry Holt and Company, 1931, 
Part II, Chap. III. 

7. Woodbridge, F. J. E., The Son of Apollo. Boston, Houghton, 

Mifflin Company, 1929. 

8. Demos, R., The Philosophy of Plato. New York, Charles Scrib- 

ner’s Sons, 1939. 

9. Post, L. A,, Thirteen Epistles of Plato. London and New York, 

Oxford University Press, 1925. 



THE SCIENCE OF ARISTOTLE 


103 

different conception of nature; and with Plato Aristotelianized, 
and Aristotle Platonized, it becomes well-nigh impossible to 
demarcate clearly the two thinkers. 

Aristotle entered Plato’s Academy at the age of eighteen. 
He came from Macedon, the rising monarchy to the north, 
where his father was court physician; and he resided at the 
Academy no less than twenty years. It is astonishing, there- 
fore, to find in Aristotle’s many allusions to Plato o^y what 
might have been derived from Plato’s published writings, as 
we know them today, and little reference to that intimate 
esoteric teaching which Plato held to be incommunicable in- 
books. Aristotle does record, it is true, a public lecture given 
by Plato on the subject of the Good; but he tells us only that 
Plato became very mathematical, mystifying his audience. 
Aristotle’s statements about Plato are those of a hostile, un- 
sympathetic, and not too well-informed critic. The twenty 
years he spent at the Academy covered the last years of 
Plato’s long life, when the aged thinker may well have 
retired from active teaching, and been immersed in public 
affairs. 

We should emphasize perhaps the early training of these two 
men, which inspired totally different interests and approaches 
to science. Plato was by birth a free and aristocratic Greek 
citizen, whose life and thought were dominated by his political 
purpose, which was the redemption of the city-state, and 
whose scientific training was in the mathematical tradition of 
Socrates, the Eleatics, and the Pythagoreans. Aristotle was a 
Macedonian subject who spent most of his life as an alien 
resident of Greek cities, whose admiration of the city-state 
was that of a disinterested outsider and beneficiary, and whose 
earliest scientific training was biological, with probably some 
knowledge of atomistic and Milesian theory. Aristotle, more- 
over, came to Athens when that city had definitely failed in 
its struggle for power, and when the city-states were over- 
shadowed by the rising monarchy to the north. Libertarian 



THE SCrENCaE OF ARISTOTLE 


105 

could be converted by a simple modification into a nontngthe- 
matical system adapted to his own interest and method. . , 

What we do mean by a development} A development is a 
temporal change having a beginning and an end. It is a unit of 
process, a real unit of change. Secondly, it is a recognizable and 
describable process, one that recurs again and again at dif- 
ferent times and places. And thirdly, it is a cumulative or di- 
rected process, one which points throughout its course to a 
certain definable goal or terminus. In organic nature develop- 
ments are ever3rwhere evident and often striking. Every living 
creature proceeds through such a development from its incep- 
tion to its maturity. Those organisms which pass through one 
and the same type of development we classify as a species. 
Thus the diverse species of organic nature indicate the dif- 
ferent sorts of organic development known to us. Today we 
do not usually speak of species when studying physical, geo- 
logical, or astronomical fact, because we conceive physical 
nature to be inorganic. But Aristotle wished to establish his 
whole science upon organic concepts such as development, 
species, etc.; and he accordingly applied the concepts in every 
field, to physical as well as to organic phenomena. 

It is by comparing individual animals and plants, in their 
visible anatomies and developmental processes, that we classify 
them into species. We may then compare these species, placing 
those which are most like each other in groups which we call 
genera (plural of genus). We can then compare genera, to 
reach higher “orders,” “families,” “kingdoms.” The animal and 
vegetable “kingdoms” have been very exhaustively classified 
in this way. The complete classification has the appearance of 
a genealogical tree, which Darwin showed it literally to be, be- 
cause the observable similarities among animals and plants, 
especially their similarities of development, are clues to their 
evolutionary origins. But imagine this specific and generic 
classification extended over all of nature, to cover also inorganic 
nature! Each organic and inorganic thing will now be under- 



THE SCIENCE OF ARISTOTLE 


107 

never overlook specific differences. It is a fact that the science 
of living organisms cannot ignore the specific forms of nature. 

But we know today that this study of the specific forms of 
organic nature leads us onward to the concept of evolution, and 
to an evolutionary science discovering the origins and muta- 
tions of the species of life. Return for a moment to the con- 
cept of development, which is the generative idea in Aristotle’s 
science, and try to universalize this concept! A development 
is a directed succession of stages a b c d,d being regarded as 
the definitive stage towards which a, b, and c are directed. To 
universalize this concept, you must conceive of the universe 
in its entirety, and in its whole history, as a vast directed ad- 
vance AB C Di You must conceive, that is to say, of a single 
vast universal evolution, advanced by every occurrence that is 
or was or will be. Such a conception is impossible, you may 
say, since every evolution requires a context or environment 
conditioning it and causally explaining it. The universe as an 
entirety cannot evolve, since by definition it has no external 
context which might condition its evolution. It may be argued 
that universal evolution is conceivable; but this is irrelevant 
to our topic, which is the science of Aristotle. Aristotle did 
not only reject the notion of a universal evolution, he re- 
jected the hypothesis of an evolution even of species. He 
allows, that is to say, only individuals to develop; and he 
allows them to develop only within the limits of their specific 
forms. Any individual aberration from the normal line of de- 
velopment, or from the fixed form and behavior characteristic 
of the species, is for him an accident devoid of scientific 
significance, and defying explanation. Aristotle’s controlling 
conception is that of a world composed of a large number of 
eternal and immutable species, made up of successive individ- 
uals which can only be understood as instances or specimens 
of these species; and so to understand things, allocating them 
to species and defining these species, he took to be the sum of 
science. 



THE SCIENCE OF AMSTOTLE IO9 

senses then again discovered in particular instances. But Ans- 
totle can insist that the specific forms of nature are apparent 
to the eye, even as they inform individual things. We actually 
see dog or cat, and immediately recognize the individual as 
a member of its species, although reasoning may be required 
to reach a satisfactory definition of the species. In this doctrine 
Aristotle is more empirical than Plato, in that he enlarges the 
role of sense-observation in science. Aristotle also believed, 
however, that the problem of the relation of form to matter dis- 
appeared in his mode of explanation. He held that the specific 
form appears in the development of the individual thing; and 
this would mean that specific forms are already resident in the 
matter which is informed by them. Aristotle, we earlier men- 
tioned, believed his concept of substance, by which he meant 
this union of form and matter in existent things, to be his great- 
est contribution to science; and we must examine this teaching 
more closely. 

The specific forms of nature, he says, although they are 
immutable and eternal, do not exist apart from the things they 
inform. They are not transcendent, like the Form of Plato, but 
have their whole being within the existent and material world. 
Form exists only in some material realization; and matter exists 
only in some specifically organized form. This would mean 
that the process of development is really the development of 
matter into some specific form; and this would seem to require 
the assumption of as many sorts of matter as there are specific 
forms or species. Aristotle is moving towards a materialistic 
philosophy in which form would be only the complete mani- 
festation of matter. He accepts this implication when he says 
that matter is potential of form, form being the realization of 
these potentialities, or potencies, of matter. Yet he never re- 
linquishes the Platonic view, which gave to form a being in its 
own right, and which saw in matter only the material which 
is shaped by form. He swings between, or overlaps, the op- 
posed views of “formism” and materialism. Thus his science 



THE SCIENCE OF AMSTOTLE 


III 


{j,.e. not formal), at least two particular causes being requited 
to bring about a particular change. Thus it is stated that a body 
will change its velocity only if some other body exerts a force 
upon it. Aristotle’s doctrine, it was finally perceived, really 
precludes and defeats causal analysis. A “specific form” is 
initially just the similarity between individuals “of the same 
species”; and we cannot suppose that the similarity of a thing 
with other things is what determines its behavior. A pup does 
not develop into a dog because there are other pups, similarly 
developing into dogs. If this were the case, the death of all 
other pups would require the death of this pup. However, it 
remains true that we discover the particular causes of natural 
occurrence by taking note of such similarities. If we want to 
know the particular causes of a particular pup’s death, we look 
around for other instances of animal mortality, similar to and 
illuminative of this instance. This suggests that there is some 
mysterious connection between the two large facts of similarity 
and causation in nature. We may not discuss the nature of this 
connection here, since our purpose is only to show how Aris- 
totle confused the concept of causation. 

These very general doctrines concemiug substance, poten- 
tiality, development, causation, and the relation of form to 
matter are presented by Aristotle in an introductory work 
which he entitled “first philosophy.” We will understand the 
doctrines better by noting Aristotle’s application of them in 
special fields; but before we turn to these special applications 
we should take note of Aristotle’s logic, which in its prescrip- 
tion of the method to be used in all scientific research consti- 
tuted a most general application of his metaphysical teaching 
or “first philosophy.” Aristotle has often been called “the 
founder of logic,” presumably because his logical treatises 
were long regarded as the definitive manual of this study, 
which they remaiued until the close of the nineteenth century. 
The EHeatics who followed Parmenides have probably more 
title to the fame of having originated logic; but Aristotle 



the science of ARISTOTIE II j 

second syllogism may be symbolized: All S is Af, no P is so 
no 5 is P. Aristotle regarded the first type of syllogism, that of 
the form: All S is Al, all Al is P, so dl S is P, as the correct 
scientific form of argument or exposition, to which all the 
other forms are auxiliary. The only reason for preferring this 
type would seem to be its conformity with the doctrine of 
definition. If the members of a group S belong to a certain 
species M, and the species M belongs to the genus P, then the 
conclusion of the syllogism will state that the group S belongs 
to the genus P. The letters S and P are chosen to indicate 
respectively the Subject and the Predicate of the conclusion; 
and M indicates the Middle term, which by appearing twice, 
once in each premise, relates the premises to each other. Aris-’ 
totelian logic is essentially an exhaustive survey of the syl- 
logisms which arise when we abide by certain formal require- 
ments, limiting us to sentences of the forms: All S is M,noS 
is M, some 5 is M, some S is not M. These syllogisms can then 
be classed as valid or invalid, according as the conclusion is or 
is not required by the premises. 

The third doctrine is that of the ccttegories. Aristotle held 
that all sentences can be classified into eight or perhaps ten 
sorts of sentence, according as to whether they predicate of 
some subject its substance, its quantity, its quality, its position 
in space or time, its action, its eiqjosure to action, etc. The 
categories would seem to indicate the ways in which the verb 
to be was used in the Greek language (this is a cat, here are 
fourteen, this is black, it is on the table, etc.) . The doctrines 
of definition and of the syllogism support one another; but the 
doctrine of the categories seems to be independent, and to 
presuppose a different conception of nature and scientific 
method. 

The Aristotelian logic remained authoritative until a gen- 
eration ago, and it still has its adherents. Most contemporary 
logicians regard it as a very hmited, wooden, and artifidfi 
exposition of the formal properties of language. It is not true, 



THE SCIENCE OF ARISTOTLE 


II5 

illustrate his basic concept of organic development. He dis- 
tinguished some organic functions as vegetative, others as 
animal because they involve locomotion and sensaton. In man, 
he tplls us, the vegetative functions support the locomotive 
and sensitive animJ functions, which in turn support the in- 
tellectual functions distinguishing man from his fellow crea- 
tures. Aristotle thinks of the development of the vegetative, 
animal, and intellectual functions as resulting from three dis- 
tinct potencies. The matter which enters into living organisms, 
he says, is of a special sort, being composed of the four material 
elements (earth, air, water, fire) together with a portion of a 
special sort of matter, the quintessence, which otherwise ap- 
pears only in celestial bodies. Thus Aristotle explicitly postu- 
lates at least three sorts of matter. There is the ordinary terres- 
trial matter which we should call inorganic; there is the celestial 
quintessence; and then there is organic matter, blended of 
these two. 

Aristotle’s biology is basic to his psychological, ethical, and 
political studies. We remember Plato’s psychology, which dis- 
tinguished in human individuals three sorts of response to 
three successively larger environments: The response to the 
immediate environment stimulates the productive and pro- 
creative functions, the response .to the state stimulates the social 
and political functions, and the response to the universe stimu- 
lates those scientific and religious interests which are the pre- 
requisite, Plato believed, of true statesmanship. Aristotle seems 
initially to accept this psychology. In his biology he defined 
man as “the animal endowed with reason,” i.e. the species which 
adds to the vegetative and animal faculties that of reasoning; 
and when he comes to discuss man further, he defines him as 
“the political animal,” which would imply that he, like Plato, 
saw in man’s political activity his distinctive character. Further, 
Aristotle presents ethics, the inquiry into what is right and 
wrong in human behavior, as only a part of the larger study 
of man which is political theory. We are accordingly surprised 





THE SCIENCE OF ARISTOTLE 


1 19 

We have not yet considered Aristotle’s physical science, 
where the limitations of his method are most apparent. Modem 
science has not recognized species in physical nature; and 
Aristotle’s insistence upon finding them there takes him to 
strange conclusions. He fell back upon the popular view, re- 
jected at least in principle by the earlier scientists, that the 
character of celestial nature is altogether different and more 
perfect than that of earthly nature. This allowed him to postu- 
late new and different principles in his explanation of celestial 
processes. For example, he calls upon a very special sort of 
matter, the quintessence, which is described as being peculiarly 
amenable to form, in order to explain the remarkable regu- 
larity of the movements of sun and stars; and he supposes that 
in the celestial realm species are normally constituted of but 
one individual member. This is really to confess the inap- 
plicability of the Aristotelian science to astronomical phe- 
nomena. Finally, the process of development becomes, in all 
of its physical realizations, only a movement of things in space, 
to or from their “proper” places in the cosmos. All motion is 
said to derive ultimately from the original circular motion 
which we perceive in the “sphere” of fixed stars. This motion 
is caused by God, who by his transcendent yet immobile Be- 
ing outside of the sphere stimulates its rotation. Circular motion 
is said to be most perfect because it is most like immobility, 
and does not involve linear displacement. This perfect motion 
is transferred with increasing irregularity and imperfection 
to interior spheres, the innermost of which is that of the 
moon’s orbit. Aristotle thinks of the heavenly bodies as the 
visible conjunctions of these otherwise invisible “crystalline 
spheres.” More than one sphere was usually required to explain 
the motion of a heavenly body. All in all, fifty-five spheres 
were called upon to explain the lunar, solar, planetary, and 
sidereal motions; and Aristotle spoke of the spheres as divinities, 
so that they constituted a pantheon of fifty-five gods. 

Below the moon the circular celestial motion is broken up 



THE SCIENCE OF ARISTOTLE 


I2I 


Further, not only must there 'be as many sorts of matter as 
there are forms, but there must also be, one would conclude, a 
most basic or rudimentary matter out of which develop the 
most general forms. Nor does Aristotle escape the tran- 
scendentalism for which he so emphatically indicts Plato. Not 
only are his eternal specific forms really transcendent, inas- 
much as one and the same specific form stimulates the develop- 
ment of a given species not only here and now, but always and 
everywhere throughout space and eternity; but all the motion 
of nature is finally attributed by Aristotle to the stimulating 
and effective presence of a God who is outside of the universe 
and no part of it. One might continue this indictment for many 
pages. One might show how Aristotle’s science, steadily dis- 
placing better science, finally resulted in intellectual stagnation 
and a scientific coma which lasted until the pioneers of modem 
science returned to Plato for their method and inspiration, and 
so overcame the sterilities of Aristotelian thought. One might 
also point to the long struggle of modern scientists against an 
ever resurgent vitalism, vitalism being nothing else than a re- 
turn to Aristotle’s ascription of causal power to specific 
forms. 

Yet after all this is said and done, we shall have to return 
to do justice to Aristotle, for three reasons. In the first place, 
there are indeed natural species, they do exist, and we cannot 
study nature without full recognition of them. Physical science 
does not really, as it may seem to do, rest its whole theory 
upon mathematical axioms. It, too, needs concepts of natural 
types, which are really species although they are not so called. 
It requires its electrons, its atoms, its chemical elements, its 
organized and specific kinds of energy. Secondly, the study of 
organic species has led to the discernment of an evolution of 
species; and the hypothesis of evolution, since it cannot be 
confined to organic nature on this earth, must ultimately give 
to all of our science a new evolutionary and organic character. 
And thirdly, if Aristotle introduced confusion into the mag- 



THE SOENCE OF ARISTOTLE 1 2} 

but not the end and purpose of life. This apparent contradic- 
tion too we must resolve. 


Notes for Further Reading 

The best and most scholarly rendering of Aristotle’s works in 
English is the Oxford Translation, recently completed. The Meta- 
physica (Vol. VIII) and the logical treatises (Vol. I) present his 
basic philosophy. Volume IX comprises his ethical, Volume X his 
political treatises. The De Anima (in Vol. Ill) is epistemologically 
important. The De Poetica, aesthetic criticism dealing with tragedy, 
will be found in Volume XI. 

There are earlier translations of many of the works. The student 
might do better to read first some studies of Aristotle by modem 
scholars. 

t. The Oxford Translation of Aristotle, ed. W. D. Ross and J. A. 
Smith. London and New York, Oxford University Press, 
various dates. 

2. Ross, W. D., Aristotle. New York, Charles Scribner’s Sons, 

1924. 

3. Gomperz, Th., Greek Thinkers, trans. G. G. Berry. London, 

J. Murray, 1914, Vol. IV, 

4. Mure, G. R. G., Aristotle. London and New York, Oxford 

University Press, 1932, 

5. Jaeger, W. W., Aristotle; Fundamentals of the History of his 

Development, trans. R. Robinson. London and New York, 
Oxford University Press, 1934. 

6. Taylor, A. E., Aristotle. A short summary. New York, Thomas 

Nelson and Sons, 1943. 

7. Zeller, Ed., Outlines of the History of Greek Philosophy, trans. 

L. R. Palmer. New York, Henry Holt and Company, 1931, 
Part II, Chap. IV. 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


125 

This nomenclature is misleading, not to say erroneous, in that 
the earlier period was often more rigorous and puritanical in 
its moral ideal. We might say, perhaps, that the later period 
pursued philosophy for its emotional inspiration, without 
scientific and mord concern for the truthful description of 
fact. The source of this shift of interest, in the writer’s opinion, 
is to be found in the changed political condition of Greece. 
Hellenic Greece was free and self-governing; its moral and 
intellectual life found realistic expression in political activities, 
and it therefore required a realistic science. But later Greece 
was politically subject, first to Macedon and then to Rome; 
and it accordingly cultivated a “reason” which elevated the 
individual as the citizen of a universal and divine polity, but 
which encouraged him to be indifferent to the social and polit- 
ical actualities about him. The living cord of liberty which 
had tied the intellectual life of Greece to actuality had been 
cut; and the Greek intellect increasingly gave itself to a 
dream. 

Nothing illustrates this movement to unrealism better than 
the uncritical homage brought to Socrates in those later cen- 
turies. Socrates had in all things tried to be a man, claiming 
no more than man might claim, dismissing the wisdom at- 
tributed to him as only his awareness of its lack; but the later 
centuries made of Socrates a god, attributing to him faculties 
beyond the range of common man. Further, Socrates had died 
to save the faith of the Greeks in their political institutions, 
i.e. in the civic law; but these later centuries made Socrates 
the martyr of the law, and the patron saint of a moral idealism 
that looked away from human government to a divine justice 
in the skies. So, for many centuries, men sought a moral salva- 
tion in no way related to government, and became indifferent 
or even hostile to law. What else could they do, so long as one 
or another imperialistic power deprived them of moral re- 
sponsibility and of its exercise in self-government? 

The broadest movement through which Socratic and other 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


127 

But Cynicism is really a transitional attitude, marking a 
shift or expansion of loyalties. If it does not develop into some- 
thing more than this antisocial revulsion, it degenerates into 
mere boorishness. So Diogenes, we read, lived in a hogshead, 
scorning every human amenity not directly provided by na- 
ture. That he was honest in his fashion we know from the 
boon he asked of Alexander, called “the Great,” who would 
have willingly pensioned him. “Just stand,” Diogenes said, 
“from between me and the sun.” Said Alexander: “If I were 
not Alexander, I would be Diogenes!” A pretty tableau! The 
sycophantic reporters hastily jot down the great man’s words, 
and rush o£F to telephone their editors! 

In Stoicism, what was true in Cynicism was broadened and 
elevated into a noble metaphysics, which became perhaps the 
best and broadest faith of that pagan world. Stoicism gets its 
name from the Stoa or Porch, the place in Athens where Zeno, 
a Semitic merchant of Cyprus, first preached this faith around 
300 B.C. Throught the writings of Epictetus, a crippled Greek 
slave, through the great Roman stylists Gcero and Seneca, and 
through the Meditations of Marcus Aurelius, who was Emperor 
of Rome at Rome’s imperial height. Stoicism came down to 
modem rimes. For some six centuries it was the chief faith of 
intellectual antiquity. 

Stoicism translated the political faith of earlier Greece into 
a “moral” faith, making the individual a citizen of the imiverse, 
subject only to universal and divine law. In its metaphysics it 
looked back of Socrates to the earlier science, although its em- 
phasis was Socratic. The human reason, it taught, discovers 
the vast economy or divine plan of the world, in which each 
individual thing has its proper place and function. Not a 
sparrow falls to earth except by divine ordination, they said. 
A man’s whole duty is to preserve himself intact from more 
proximate stimuli, which mislead and destroy him, and to live 
wholly in the light of this rational knowledge of universal 
nature; for man’s integrity is his reason, at once theoretical and 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


129 

earlier directed Greek philosophy were no longer remembered, 
they persisted subconsciously; and they come strangely and 
importantly to Ught in the Stoic vocabulary. The universe, 
said the Stoic, is the great City of God, a realm of moral in- 
dividuals ruled by divine justice. The Stoics were not tran- 
scendentalists like Plato. Their City of God did not exist only 
in the skies or beyond. It is the actual material universe which 
now and everywhere exists, but which only reason discerns. 
It is a City without a written code, a divine community need- 
ing neither church nor priesthood, and which no earthly ca- 
tastrophe can harm. All men are by birth the citizens of this 
visible-invisible realm, so replete with light, beauty, law, good- 
ness. The eternal and divine constitution of the world is wholly 
realized in every part of the world. The sole evil is our failure 
to recognize this goodness. Stoicism reacted to the political 
failure of antique society with a renewed confession of faith. 
The free cities had fallen; but the free City of God, which is 
the universe itself, remained undisturbed, and provided a 
home for man. Spinoza would later dream this dream again. 

This tremendous loyalty, one might argue, excuses every 
defect of Stoicism — ^its confused metaphysic, in which nature 
is at once natural law and what conforms to natural law; its 
bankruptcy of affection, excused by moral casuistry; its facile 
catholicity, allegorizing every teaching into its own. Stoicism 
first consoled the Greek who had lost his freedom, restoring 
his self-respect; then it broadened Roman justice; finally it 
prepared the way for universalistic Christianity. It was the 
widest channel through which there flowed to posterity the 
Greek faith in a justice which is truth. Yet our appreciation of 
the nobility and generosity of this Stoic faith, and of its en- 
nobling influence upon the later centuries and our consequent 
debt to it, should not blind us to its great defect, which was 
its moral unrealism. The Stoic taught that the world is even 
now perfect, in spite of all apparent evil. The difference be- 
tween good and evil, this suggests, is subjective and illusory; 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY I3I 

Some of their scholars took advantage of the wide and eclectic 
character of Stoic doctrine to develop a very empirical theory 
of knowledge. All knowledge, these men taught, comes from 
experience, the mind being initially a blank tablet upon which 
impressions are left by observed particular things; and memory 
and inference then allow the advance from these particular 
impressions to the general concepts of a universal science. This 
epistemology was revived at the beginning of the modern age 
to support the philosophy of empincism\ and it led some of the 
Stoics, as it was later to lead Berkeley and Hume, to skeptical 
conclusions. To avoid these, they vaguely appealed to “com- 
mon sense,” by which they meant a faculty to apprehend 
general forms. Here they followed Aristotle. Stoic thinkers 
also developed the Aristotelian logic, in particular the doctrine 
of the categories, and the important properties of conditional 
sentences of the form; If A, then B. The Stoic epistemology 
and logic helped the pioneers of modem thought to break 
away from the scholastic philosophy of the Middle Ages, and 
they have continued to play an important part in later 
philosophy. 

The great virtue of Stoicism, we said, was its universalistic 
humanism. The earlier Greeks were humanistic in their respect 
for the human “essence” which dwells in every human in- 
dividual; but they tended to identify humanity with the Greek 
people, leaving “barbarians” outside the pale. These Hellenistic 
Greeks made no such distinction. Semite and Greek, slave and 
master, commoner and emperor, halt and whole were equally 
citizens of “the blessed City of God,” and children of the God 
in whom all things “live and move and have their being.” This 
hospitable humanism, however, was facilitated and made futile 
by political indifference. They affirmed human equality, but 
they did not draw the political implications of this doctrine. 
They tolerated every sort of economic and political disfran- 
chisement. Nevertheless this merely verbal equalitarianism was 
not without some realistic consequence. The slave was finally 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


m 

Under the Empire, the city of Rome became increasingly a 
court of last appeal for cases not covered by provincial laws. 
The Roman jurists used Stoic principles in their creation of a 
law of equity, the jus gentiimt or “law of peoples.” This Roman 
jurisprudence — ^not to be confused with the old civic law of 
Rome — was codified under Justinian in the sixth century a.d.; 
and as “Roman law,” never forgotten in the Italian law schools, 
it deeply influenced the development throughout Europe of 
the concept of justice. Through Cicero and through Roman 
law, the Stoic concept of equalitarian and universal citizenship 
began its descent to earth, to become after many centuries the 
theory of democratic society. 

A second Socratic development, existing alongside of 
Stoicism through these later centuries of antiquity, was 
Epicureanism. Much as Stoicism corrected and enlarged 
Cynicism, the Epicureans elaborated the hedonistic doctrine of 
Aristippus of Cyrene. {Hedonism is any doctrine which finds 
pleasure to be the substance or criterion of goodness.) Aris- 
tippus had come to Socrates from Protagoras, and he seems 
to have seen in Socrates only a more able sophist, appealing 
against convention and law to some purely individual and sub- 
jective insight into truth. Whereas the Cynics found this cri- 
terion in the individual’s moral sense of self-integrity, Aristip- 
pus found it in the immediate conscious apprehension of value, 
i.e. in pleasure. Man’s reason, Aristippus implied, is his ability 
to calculate, aided by memory and anticipation, the conse- 
quences of his conduct; but hi criterion of what is good for 
him must be a deeper, personal, and natural instinct, common 
to man and the animals. Every creature is endowed with sensi- 
tivity to pleasure and pain, which tells it what to pursue and 
what to avoid; but man, by means of his reason, is able to 
apply this instinctive faculty widely and precisely, by weigh- 
ing pleasures and pains and calculating an optimum synthesis. 

Hedonism usually has received hard treatment from mo- 
ralists, who are apt to find in it only a defense of license. The 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


135 

observe, by comparing and contrasting the Cyrenaic and 
Cynic doctrines, their common error, which was their isolation 
of the individual from his moral context in society. This isola- 
tion left their ethics arbitrary and wilful. The Cyrenaic could 
equate the good with pleasure, the Cynic could equate it with 
aloofness from pleasure. Each of the doctrines confused reality 
with one or the other of the two criteria of reality, with im- 
mediate experience or with logic, 

Epicurus rescued the truth which lay in the Cyrenaic 
hedonism by replacing the individual in his social and natural 
context. Bom and brought up like Pythagoras in the isle of 
Samos off the Ionian coast, Epicurus came to the mainland of 
Greece for his education. Samos had earlier escaped the horrors 
of the long war; but on his return he found it ruined and 
desolate. Epicurus evidently experienced a deep revulsion 
against the cultured, educated, but hectic and irresponsible 
world which bred these wars. He hated the great world with 
its grandiloquent and deadly superstitions — ^its idols religious, 
political, scientific. He taught sobriety, and established his 
“gardens” in which humble, sane, and loving people could take 
refuge from the world, scorning its prizes and its feverish am- 
bition. In these Epicurean groves all was plainness, simplicity, 
and friendship. Men and women lived as nature intended them 
to live, satisfied with normal pleasures, healthy with work, 
blessed with human community. 

The essential doctrine of Epicurus was that of human free- 
dom. There is no just power, he taught, which has authority 
over man. The human individual is properly a natural unit, a 
self-determined and self-controlled absolute. His whole duty 
is to himself, since there is no higher unit of which he is a 
part. His virtue is self-preservation and self-discipline; and he is 
wholly responsible to himself for his conduct. Virtue, there- 
fore, even as Socrates taught, is just sane and intelligent living. 
To establish this doctrine Epicurus appropriated the atomis- 
tic science, rejecting all other Greek science. His intention 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


137 

obviously, of course, atomism fails to account for the existence 
of a life cognitive of its ovm conditions. The ascription of 
consciousness to atoms or atomic collocations would cause the 
collapse of the atomistic view, if this consciousness is allowed to 
influence their behavior. The failure of Epicurus to see the 
social and metaphysical implications of his individualistic creed 
caused the degeneration of Epicureanism. When memory of 
the noble hfe of its founder waned, there was left the cult of 
refined sensuality which the name “Epicurean” connotes today. 
But we may beheve that Epicurus had truer descendants in the 
early Christians, whose cult of the community of friends 
bound by mutual love revived his central teaching. 

A secondary Epicurean doctrine was to have important uses 
in later times. The early Epicureans withdrew from the world, 
but they still had to adjust themselves to politically organized 
society. To guide or justify their dealings with governments 
they developed the sophistic view, which held law to be but 
convention imposed upon the individual by force, into the 
more self-respecting and reasonable theory that government 
arises out of a business contract, entered into by individuals 
for the performance of certain specific common functions such 
as police duty and military protection. The intention of this 
contract-theory was to deprive government of all intrinsic 
authority, especially religious and moral authority, yet to justify 
government as an economic utility. Recovered in the later 
Middle Ages and curiously associated with biblical ideas of a 
covenant binding God and man, this contract-theory became 
an important element of modern political thought, where it 
supports the doctrine of government by consent and the in- 
sistence upon moral limitadons upon government. 

It was chiefly through the Roman poet Lucretius that knowl- 
edge of Epicurean doctrine came to later Europe. In his great 
Latin epic De Return Natura Lucretius gave to the doctrine 
a new and ennobling purpose. The rejection of superstition 
becomes a positive adoration of scientific truth, and the provin- 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


139 

emphasized especially the mystical elements in the Platonic 
teaching. Further, Philo was influenced by the method of in- 
terpretation developed by the Stoics, who accepted many re- 
ligious creeds as allegorical versions of their more theoretical 
faith. Thus Philo believed (as Roger Bacon much later was to 
believe) that Plato and Moses offered different versions of one 
and the same truth. The hospitable but uncritical attitude of 
mind supporting this belief is characteristic of these later cen- 
turies of antiquity, when men were seeking a faith which might 
unite into cultural homogeneity that motley Mediterranean 
world. The deepest cleft in the cultural landscape was the 
chasm between Greek and Semitic cultures, as we shall ob- 
serve in our discussion of Christianity; and it was this chasm 
that Philo wished to bridge. 

Similarly characteristic of all of these centuries is the lack 
of scientific interest which marked Neoplatonism. The dom- 
inating interest is moral and religious, in the unfortunate sense 
which divorces morality and religion from science. Philo’s in- 
terest was intellectual, since he required a conceptual approach 
to truth; but his dominating objective was the moral and re- 
ligious salvation of the individual, to which the conceptual 
approach must lead. He is no scientist like Plato, who required 
reason to “save the appearances,” i.e. to illuminate particular 
and observable fact; but he used the largest framework of 
Platonic and Aristotelian science as a conceptual ladder, up 
which the inquiring mind might ascend in order, from its high- 
est rung, to leap off into a mystical communion or mergence 
with absolute Being, this ecstatic vision being the sole motive 
and reason of the intellectual effort of man. 

Argument as to whether Plato was correctly understood by 
Philo would be inconclusive, since the difference is essentially 
one of emphasis. Plato established a school of science and law, 
the Neoplatonists established theology. But more important 
than this epistemological difference was the shift in metaphysi- 
cal doctrine. Plato was uncompromisingly dualisdc in his dis- 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


I4I 

with the lines: “In the beg^ning 'was the Word [Logos'\, and 
the Word 'was 'with God, and the Word 'was God . . . And 
the Word 'was made -flesh, and d-welt among us (and 'we beheld 
Ms glory, the glory as of the only begotten of the Father), 
full of grace and truth” So, of Philo and of John, elder of the 
church at Alexandria, was born Christian theology. 

Evidently, this Neoplatonic version of Plato persisted in 
Alexandrian thought from the beginning of the Christian era; 
but it reached its full elaboration only in the third century A.D., 
through Plotinus and Origen, pupils both of one Ammonius 
Saccas of Alexandria. Plotinus is usually regarded as the au- 
thoritative exponent, his writings being edited and published 
by his pupil Porphyry in a work since called the Enneads from 
its division into nine books. The work is a beautiful fantasy, 
full of light and color and suggestive metaphor, warm with 
moral aspiration and religious anticipation. It is certainly not 
science, and scarcely philosophy, since its speculation is almost 
wholly uncritical, and weaves together with eclectic liberality 
half a dozen brilliant strands of earlier Greek speculation. The 
method is wholly deductive and nonempirical, moving from 
the intuition of ultimate Being downward (whereas empirical 
thought moves upward from observed particulars to ever more 
general principles); and very much as Hegel later was to 
weave into his speculative fantasy the concepts of contempo- 
rary science, so Plotinus finds room on his celestial ladder of 
form for Ionian, Pythagorean, Stoic, Aristotelian, Eleatic, and 
other concepts. From God, the infinite and iaeffable, there 
moves nous or reason, the articulate thought of God with its 
plurality of forms or ideas. (It is from Neoplatonism that the 
word “idea” gets its present meaning. Earlier it had meant 
“form” or even “shape,” something objective which might be 
known but which was not peculiarly mental in itself.) The 
divine ideas are eternal or timeless, they define the five cate- 
gories or ways of being, and they generate a cloud of mystical 
numbers, of which there is one for each species, and one for 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 1 43 

Christian creed. There were, further, numerous encyclopedias 
of Greek thought, and commentaries on earlier Greek thinkers, 
written by Neoplatonists between the third and the sixth cen- 
turies, and preserved by the church when earlier writings were 
lost. Thus it was that philosophy came to be identified with 
Neoplatonic mysticism; and although after a millennium 
Europe was to enjoy again a firsthand knowledge of classical 
Greece, it still read the Greek originals through Neoplatonic 
spectacles. Nor has it ever fully emancipated itself from that 
influence. To this day philosophy remains either shaped by the 
Neoplatonic tradition, or in a revulsion against it so violent that 
the Platonic insight is often rejected along with the Neoplatonic 
fantasy; and seldom, except amongst a few scholars versed in 
Greek, does one find any adequate knowledge and just esti- 
mate of Greek science. 

The result is that in spite of our professed admiration for 
the Greek achievement, we have never done justice to it nor 
appropriated its greatest values. We look back to Greek art 
with its delicacy and poise, its lyrical poignancy, its sense of 
the audacious right word, its Homeric complacency; but we 
do not see clearly the Greece that gave us a realistic science 
and a realistic ethics, the Greece that nursed Socrates and 
Plato and their great predecessors. Plotinus was not Greece, 
even Aristotle was no true Greek. That other Greece was 
rugged, plain, sober; yet it too was poignant in its moral hunger, 
and more audacious than any Greek simile in its demand for a 
religion that served justice first and last. There was in the great- 
est Greek thinkers an incomparable honesty, a realism that has 
never been surpassed; and the honesty of Greece is half of 
the great heritage which is the source of all our blessing. Only 
in Plato do we know with some familiarity and completeness 
the superb mind and spirit, the sublime truthfulness that was 
early Greece. 

From Greece came theoretical science, the mother of all 
science, and one of the two great bulwarks of the modem 
world. There is no reason to believe that factories and dynamos 



HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY 


HS 

3. Fuller, B. A. G., A History of Ancient and Medieval Philos- 

ophy. New York, Henry Holt and Company, 1938, revised 
1945, Chaps, VI, VII. 

4. Bevan, E. R., Stoics and Sceptics. London and New York, 

Oxford University Press, 1913. 

5. The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Antoninus. Many edi- 

tions. 

<5. Wenley, R. M., Stoicism and Its Influence. Boston, Longmans, 
Green and Company, 1927. 

7. Inge, W. R., Plotinus. Boston, Longmans, Green and Com- 

pany, 1918. 

8. Patrick, M. M., The Greek Sceptics. New York, Columbia 

University Press, 1929. 

9. Lucretius, De rerum natura, trans. P. Bailey, London and New 

York, Oxford University Press, 1904, also translations by 
Munro, Leonard, and others. 

10. Santayana, G., Three Philosophical Poets. Cambridge, Harvard 

University Press, 1910. 

11. Taylor, A. E., Epicurus. New York, Dodge Publishing Com- 

pany, 1910. 

12. Wallace, W., Epicureanism. London, Society for Promotion of 

Christian Knowledge, 1880. 



n THE AOTECEDENTS OF 
MODERN PHILOSOPHY 



9 A NEW HEAVEN 
AND A NEW EARTH 


Is THE INTEIXECTUAI- AND MORAL CONFUSION OF TODAY 
the result of our erroneous belief that we can continue 
to enjoy the fruits of a religious past without acknowledging 
their religious source? Was it religion that gave to this modem 
era its great impetus, generated by a millennium of great faith? 
It was necessary, in order to allow this faith to reach its full 
realization, to emancipate religion from its institutional forms, 
its dogmatic creeds, and its closed ecclesiastical organization. 
This emancipation required the disestablishment of institutions 
which for many had become identified with religion itself. But 
might it not be argued that what was emancipated and em- 
powered by the Reformation and the Renaissance was just 
religious truth itself, in its essential sanity and power? Should 
we imagine that a purely secular culture has expressed itself in 
the social and scientific achievements of the last four centuries? 
It may be that the virtues of tolerance, kindness, justice, and 
mercy will not persist in individual and social life if we no 
longer remember their historical evolution and their religious 
source. It is scarcely to be denied that what there is of culture 
or civilization in modem society is of Christian origin; and 


149 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 


151 

and their causal connections. Neither religious indifference nor 
religious unbelief should deter the social scientist from im- 
partial study and objective estimate of the working of religion 
in human liistory. It is a fact that for nearly two thousand 
years, religious faith chiefly determined the direction of social 
evolution in the western world; and the effort to recover this 
history without full acknowledgment of its religious stimula- 
tion merely leaves the historian impotent and his narrative 
trivial and tedious. Religious beliefs impelled or conditioned all 
the moral, political, and economic history of the west. One 
cannot set forth the long movement of western man to his 
present form of society without continuous reference to Chris- 
tian tenets. This does not mean, of course, that the historian 
should identify his own faith with that of Christianity. As a 
historian, he must remain free from every religious preposses- 
sion. But he does not obtain this freedom by ignoring the de- 
gree to which religious faith, for better or for worse, has molded 
history. His business as a historian is to state what actually 
occurred, and to discover what caused what. It is accordingly 
his duty to register and estimate the effects of religion upon 
political and other history, where religion had such effects. 
He may properly abstain from any explicit conclusion regard- 
ing the truth or error of the faith which had these effects; 
but he will scarcely find it possible to avoid all estimate of 
those effects as good, bad, or indifferent. In any case, those 
who read his history will draw such conclusions, since the good 
or evil fruits of a faith are evidence for or against its truth. A 
faith that destroys or weakens society cannot be true; a faith 
that strengthens and invigorates society may be true. Historical 
impartiality means honest judgment, not abstention from 
judgment, with respect to religion. Complete reservation of 
judgment is just intellectual cowardice. 

By any historical measure, the rise and spread of Christianity 
was a social revolution of the first magnitude. The Roman 
empire, the greatest and stablest political organization human 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 1 53 

destruction of Judaea was Rome’s final abdication, and the 
passage of power from imperial to papal hands. 

Roman history is an object lesson in the sources of political 
power, and the conditions of its retention. The Jewish people 
were set apart from other peoples by a rigid and fierce loyalty 
to their religious and national past. For more than three cen- 
turies, however, ever since the conquests of Alexander, they 
had been directly exposed to foreign influences, including that 
of the Greek mystery-religions. Among Grecianized Jews 
there appeared a new cult which combined the intensity of 
the Jewish faith, focused now upon a Messiah who would 
carry Judaea to victory, with the more personal ardor of the 
mystery-religions, which offered salvation to the individual 
through the mediation of a divine Savior or Christ. The new 
faith was Pythagorean, at once individualistic and social. It 
taught the redemption of a Christian community, composed of 
all those individuals who accepted the atonement of Christ. 
After a sharp struggle, this Christian faith was carried by some 
of its Jewish proponents to the gentile world. Because the 
Jewish people had established important colonies in all of the 
larger Mediterranean cities, the propagation of Christianity 
proceeded from many centers and was accordingly rapid. With 
the destruction of Judaea in a.d. 70 Christianity became defi- 
nitely hostile to Rome, this attitude finding its earliest expres- 
sion in the Book of the Revelation of John, later included in 
the Christian Bible. This writing was dedicated to the seven 
churches of Asia Minor, the chief center of early Christianity; 
and it foretells the destruction of “Babylon,” meaning Rome, 
to make room for “a new heaven and a new earth.” 

Very rapidly this Christian cult spread, until it reached the 
remote outposts of the far-flung Roman world; and steadily it 
gathered into itself what was best in that world. What did it 
offer to its faithful, whom it exposed to contempt, ostracism, 
persecution, and death? Why did it gain ground in spite of the 
opposition of politically organized power? It is evident that 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 155 

law” and to follow instead the admonitions of “the spirit.” 
What was this “spirit,” which transcended all law and all the 
past? 

The spirit, said Foul of Tarsus, who first carried this radical 
gospel to the gentile world, is the faith, hope, and love which 
transforms a group of random individuals into a living com- 
munity, solid and impulsive yet free. Here were three new 
“virtues”; and their establishment as such constituted a new 
theory of human nature. You must throw off your old nature, 
said Paul, and put on a new nature. Was this doctrine less 
momentous two thousand years ago than today, when it is 
revived in perverted forms? To appropriate the new nature, 
concluded Paul, you need only accept the atonement and 
example of Jesus Christ, the new man who is also God. Faith 
in the godhead of Jesus Christ is the suflScient condition of the 
three virtues of faith, hope, and love, which in their turn are 
the constitutive properties of the new man and the new so- 
ciety. Did Paul merely use the figure of Jesus, as Plato is 
sometimes held to have used the figure of Socrates, to express 
his own ideas and to advance his own purposes? Or shall we 
too say that Jesus Christ was the divine and creative seed out 
of which grew a new civilization? This was not the only time 
that such claims have been made for a human individual; but 
it was perhaps the only time in human history that such claims, 
widely allowed, have revolutionized civilization. 

It is fairly well agreed among exegetical scholars that the 
earliest Christian conceptions, even those presented in the New 
Testament, are an inseparable amalgam of historical fact and 
imaginative interpretation. In one sense there is nothing new 
in the New Testament. No dictum there that has not its 
analogue in earlier wisdom, no incident that is not reminiscent 
of earlier myth, no concept that is not implicit in some earlier 
train of thought! The New Testament could conceivably be 
the imaginative creation of a gifted group of audacious seekers 
after religious truth. It could be a synthesis of earlier religious 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 1 57 

The Stoics had allowed that man might live and move and 
have his being in God; but only Jesus, carrying to its full con- 
clusion the Socratic teaching that piety is the love of God, 
dared to teach that God might live and move and have his 
being in individual man. Perhaps this is blasphemy still. What- 
ever it be, it is nevertheless the creed by which Jesus Christ 
brought to an end the pagan world, and announced the re- 
ligious basis upon which our modem world is established; for 
what Jesus revealed is the truth that man is in his own nature 
divine, free, and creative, even as is God. How, except on this 
awful, audacious, and sobering assumption, should the human 
individual exercise moral and intellectual responsibility? Yet 
upon this exercise of individual responsibility we have estab- 
lished our society and our science. Let the modem thinker make 
explicit the religious and metaphysical implications of the fact 
of individual responsibility, which is the foundation and presup- 
position of modem life! 

The first of the Christian virtues, accordingly, is faith in 
the divinity of man. Christianity was a humanism which af- 
firmed God even in its afiirmation of human rights. It saw in 
Jesus, whom it called “Christ,” the protagonist and exemplar 
of this faith that man is in his incalculable measure God. It 
taught that we shall find God if we will look for Him in the 
lineaments of men and women, boys and girls. The kingdom 
of heaven is within man, not in the sky. 

The second of the Christian virtues was its optimism, its 
hope. This optimism is once again our faith in creative man, 
relieved of the intolerable burden of past failure. Hope is our 
natural orientation upon the future; for to be so oriented is to 
recognize, intelligently and explicitly, the instinctive momen- 
tum of our flesh and blood, and to affirm, and not obstruct, 
our essential nature. We have forgotten, just because Chris- 
tianity is still our teacher, how afflicted with nostalgia and 
pessimism was all antiquity. Before Christ all goodness was 
residue, the golden age was a remote past, the present was a 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 159 

t. ] fgi ggrir:al system, which from the fifth to the fifteenth cen- 
txiry was to be the chief agency of government in Europe, 
exercising powers coordinate with or superior to those of 
secular rulers. Since ecclesiasticism, like feudalism, has been a 
stage or tendency in every large social evolution, we need not 
suppose that there is any especi^y close bond between ec- 
clesiastical form and Christian tenets. What most strikingly 
distinguishes Christianity from other faiths, indeed, is its ex- 
plosive exodus, after a thousand years of vigorous development, 
from the eccelesiastical institution which had so long protected 
and directed its growth. 

The historian should not, of course, overlook the great 
achievements of ecclesiastical Christianity, and the inestimable 
service it rendered to the long Middle Ages and through them 
to ourselves. When the Roman economy collapsed, and the 
peoples of central and northern Europe came tumbling into 
what had been the Empire, it was the church that educated this 
new Europe, not only in literary arts and in religious embol- 
ism, but also in agriculture, building, and every economic 
skill. For a thousand years the church educated Europe. It pre- 
served and propagated the political genius inherited from im- 
perial Rome, providing ministers of state more educated and 
humane than their royal masters. For a thousand years it guided 
and moderated secular governments. And during this long 
period it firmly inculcated the truth, which Europe was not to 
Wget until this twentieth century, that there stands above all 
kings and govenunents a moral authority which no political 
power may exert. Modem society could establish itself only 
after the disestablishment of ecclesiastical authority; but die 
free modern society which replaced medieval ecclesiasticism 
was, even in its libertarian rebellion, the child of that church, 
to which we must stiU owe a filial gratitude. Not to bring this 
gratitude is to lack spiritual maturity, and to have no claim to 
religious and intellectual liberty. Only what honors its origins 
lives long on this earth. 

But the chief concern of this chapter is the intellectual 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 


i6i 

men from other individuals on the ground of their rational 
faculty. But this emphasis upon human individuality had always 
been a sort of joint or hinge in Greek philosophy, because it 
could not be derived from the still more basic conception which 
saw in individual things only the local and imperfect appear- 
ances of eternal and universal Being. Christianity went still 
further in its high evaluation of the human individual; and it 
did not identify what is eternal in the human individual with 
the theorizing intellect. Its conception of nature as a great 
drama of temporal creation required the attribution of some 
sort of absoluteness to individual being, in that it made indi- 
viduals, and not specific or other eternal forms, the directive 
agencies of natural occurrence. 

But the opposition between the new Christian concept of 
nature and the old Greek etemalism, although it was doubtless 
vividly felt, could not be easily stated, or immediately grasped 
in its tremendous implication; and the new faith had to make 
some sort of contact with the long intellectual tradition of 
antiquity, which still dominated the intellectual life of that 
time. So we find Christianity seeking to adapt its language to 
that of traditional Greek philosophy, and even to present its 
very different conception in terms of that philosophy. Neo- 
platonism, as the form of Greek philosophy most familiar to 
educated Christians, provided the vocabulary used to introduce 
Christian thought to intellectual society. At the beginning of 
the third century there was elaborated, chiefly by Origen, the 
pupil of Neoplatonist Ammonius Saccas in Alexandria, the 
Cluistian theology which for many centuries would largely 
replace, as authoritative Christian creed, the simpler and 
mightier faith affirmed in the earlier scriptures. The junction 
between Christian faith and Greek philosophy was effected by 
means of the doctrine of the Trinity, which interpreted the 
relation of Jesus Christ to God and to man in terms of the three 
highest forms of the Neoplatonic hierarchy of being. The 
supreme Being became God the Father or Jehovah; the Logos 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 


163 

tual difficulties. It is evident to the reader of his Confessions 
that Augustine’s problem was a personal one. A man of excep- 
tional intellectual power, he had found no great work to do, no 
lasting and cumulative purpose which would give substance 
and perhaps immortality to his achievements. The young and 
vigorous church offered the vehicle for his talents that he 
needed. What he gave to that church would go far, and be 
conserved perhaps forever. Just because Augustine was indi- 
vidualistic to the point of egoism, it was altogether essential for 
him to lose himself in a life greater than his own. In the church, 
he tells us, he found the release for his energies and the serenity 
of mind he had sought elsewhere in vain; and the egoist of the 
Confessions became the immortal author of The City of God. 

Looking back to Augustine today, we see in him the proto- 
type of modem man. He stands alongside Plato as the second 
of the two thinkers who have most forcefully determined our 
intellectual evolution; and with each year, as we more clearly 
grasp the constitution of this modem age, the figure of Augus- 
tine increases in stature. Unlike Plato, who consummated the 
thought of Greece, Augustine stands at the beginning of the 
intellectual age which is our own. No great systematist, his 
greatness lay in his grasp, seldom clear but ultimately effective, 
of the new conception of reality which moved in the Christian 
faith. Limited though he was by the vocabulary of Greek 
philosophy, Augustine was nevertheless able to in^cate a new 
sort of apprehension of actuality. He accomplished this by 
implication and suggestion. He gave to old concepts new mean- 
ings, he bluntly rejected certain hitherto dominant concepts, 
and he created some new concepts. In their sum, these changes 
successfully communicated the new concept of reality which 
engendered them. It is scarcely too much to say that the history 
of thought since Augustine, especially the thought of the last 
six centuries, has been the straggle between Greek eternalism 
and Augustinian creationism; and today we must acknowledge 
Augustine the victor in this struggle. 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 


165 

don of the human, race through the creative agency of Jesus 
Christ and the church. Yet he never quite rejected the eter- 
nalistic theology of the earlier Fathers, who spoke of the world 
as the materialization of the timeless ideas of the Logos or the* 
mind of God. However, Augustine’s greatest and best-known 
work. The City of God, very definitely advanced a temporal- 
istic or historical conception of reality. In this book the biblical 
story of the creation, fall, and redemption of man is expanded 
into a philosophy of history, which uses the narrative and 
prophecy of the Old Testament to portray a long struggle of 
earthly empires as the prelude to the advent of the true and 
divine government of man in the church. The Roman Empire 
is depicted as the latest embodiment of the powers of error and 
evil in the world; and Augustine hopefully anticipated, as well 
he might early in the fifth century, its final collapse. Augustine 
was not the first thinker to make use of history as a vehicle of 
philosophical truth; but he was the thinker through whom this 
philosophical approach, which earlier ages called “prophecy,” 
was chiefly developed and transmitted to later times. 

Augustine’s reading of history as a long progress from more 
secular to more spiritual government is often dismissed by 
modem critics as a flagrant example of fatalistic or teleological 
explanation. Whereas science mechanistically explains later 
events as effects of earlier events which are their causes, the 
teleologist explains earlier events as the necessary antecedents 
of certain later events, their goal. Teleology, in short, extends, 
the concept of purposive behavior to wider nature, as if vast 
namre revealed some purpose of its own. Thus for Augustine 
material nature was created to provide a home for the human 
spirit, and the long centuries of human error are shown to be 
tile working of the will of God, who has deter mi ned man’s sal- 
vation. It cannot be denied that Augustine does explain the his- 
tory of nature teleologically, as leading up to its divinely in- 
tended goal or terminus; but the critic is incautious when he 
hastily assumes that such explanation is necessarily unscien- 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 1 67 

Since all science and society are established upon these two 
apparently contradictory doctrines, it is for the honest and 
courageous thinker to attempt their reconciliation, by showing 
how their apparent contradiction can be removed. We do not 
further understanding by affirming one of the two doctrines, 
while glibly ignoring the other. 

The intention of early Christianity was to extol spontaneous 
goodness, immediate responsiveness, ready feeling. It advocated 
more “life,” i.e. more sensitiveness to the immediate present. It 
opposed “the spirit” to “the law,” the claim of the present or 
future to the claim of the dead past. This attitude was and is 
deeply philosophical — ^however, it is philosophical in a sense 
directly opposed to ancient philosophy, which had always 
deprecated the present in the interests of the “eternal,” l.e. the 
past. Therefore Christianity in its most essential doctrine, that 
of the spirit which fulfils and transcends the law, could not be 
absorbed into Greek philosophy; and it has always reacted with 
and upon Greek philosophy in significant and profitable ways. 
One of these ways has been its emphasis upon individual 
character. To subordinate the law to the needs of living men 
and women is ultimately to make individuals the source and 
criterion of law. 

This individualism appears both implicitly and explicitly in 
Augustine’s writings. It is imphcit in his autobiographical 
Confessions. These, with their unrelieved and somewhat egoistic 
concern for the salvation of their author, are the prototype of 
the psychological literature widely current in our own day. 
No other work of antiquity is so modem in quality as this. 
Augustine shows here little awareness of the society around 
him, the well-being of which is the real goal of all his moral 
effort. He is concerned only with his own soul and its redemp- 
tion; yet the solution of his private problem is his entrance into 
the Christian community, in which his individual life is identi- 
fied, by an act of free wiU, with the larger life of the church. 

More explicit is the individualism of Augustine’s theory of 



A NEW HEAVEN AND A NEW EARTH 


169 

and love of truth, Augustine is able to argue the reality of God 
who created the world and implanted in us our love of truth. 
Descartes, early in the seventeenth century, revived this Augus- 
tinian doctrine, which has given to all modem thought its dis- 
tinctive subjective character. 

Augustine was the first great and original thinker, if we 
except Lucretius, who used the Latin language. The use of 
Latin affected western thought, since Greek concepts undergo 
some modification even in their nearest Latin rendering; but 
more important is the great influence which this use of Latin 
gave to Augustine in the west, where Latin was to be the 
language of scholarship for more than a thousand years It is 
difficult to overemphasize this Augustinian influence in the 
development of western thought and life. The earlier Church 
Fathers had tied Christian theology to the rationalistic Neopla- 
tonic philosophy. Augustine did not repudiate the earlier 
theology; yet he liberated himself from it, and liberated finally 
the thought of the west, by appending to it the individualistic, 
empirical, and creationistic doctrines we have noted. 

The greamess of Augustine, and the enormous part he played 
in the shaping of western thought, are beconoing recognized 
today. The positive and revolutionary character of his thought 
was not immediately apparent, for he usually said less than his 
doctrines implied. He retained the older theology alongside his 
own radical tenets; and he never, because he could not have 
done so, adds up his radical innovations and emphases to pro- 
duce a total picture. But when, fifteen hundred years later, we 
try to sum up the modifications introduced by this remarkable 
thinker, in order to grasp the integral concept of reality which 
inspired and emboldened his thought, we are startled to find 
how different from that of any earlier thinker, and how like 
our own, was Augustine’s vision of the world. This man, we 
conclude, was the first “modern”! And then we discover how, 
in historical fact, the thought of Augustine stimulated the late 
medieval movements which ushered in modern science and 



10 THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 


W HAVE NOW OBSERVED THE DEVELOPMENT OF 

Greek science, in its effort to establish a universal 
knowledge grounding a just civic constitution; we have seen 
how realistic thought, following Aristotle, became idealistic, 
natural science becoming a moral system and the ideal constitu- 
tion becoming a city of the sky; and we have finally noted how 
Christianity cut across this Greek movement at an oblique 
angle, retaining and even accentuating its moral emphasis, yet 
requiring a realistic actualization of the moral ideal in a re- 
deemed human community. The final result of the long devel- 
opment was the establishment of a universal church, armed 
with a moral or spiritual authority which claimed precedence 
over secular power. To Caesar should be rendered what is 
Caesar’s, and to God what is God’s. To God, announced the 
Christian prayer, belongs the kingdom, the power, and the 
glory forever! Just what was assigned to Caesar? 

For a thousand years the ecclesiastical organization centered 
at Rome retained this authority, and western Europe developed 
under a dual government of church and state. The complex 
relationship between the ecclesiastical and secular governments 
is the central theme of the long medieval history; and this rela- 
tionship continues to play a much larger part than is usually 

171 



the long middle age lyj 

- stagnancy, and not to be revived except by a return to the social 
and political poverty out of which they arose. 

Feudalism appears at an early stage of many a developing 
civilization. When the western Roman Empire, separated now 
from the eastern Empire centered at Constantinople, fell into 
chaos as the result of turbulent migrations from northern and 
central Europe, a measure of order and stability was reached 
where local chieftains could establish their power by rigid 
military rule. As chaos lessened and migrating peoples turned 
to settlement and agriculture, military discipline became a sys- 
tem of land tenure, the ownership of land carr5dng military 
responsibilities. This was feudalism, a loose system of personal 
government which could and did develop into the great feudal 
hierarchy of emperor, kings, princes, lords, knights, squires, 
yeomen, and serfs. Normally, i.e. with peace and the develop- 
ment of artisanship and commerce, feudal government is 
steadily transformed into something else, even where the feudal 
forms and titles are retained. It should be observed that feudal 
government, although personal, is not absolute government. 
Each level of the feudal hierarchy has its rights as well as its 
responsibilities, and it is the duty of the individual to maintain 
these feudal rights, established by use or common law, against 
aggression from above and invasion from below. When war 
and the constant threat of war gave way to more peaceful pros- 
pects, the feudal system became artificial and self-destructive, 
corrupting into “chivalry” and bloody vendettas between 
noble families. The Wars of the Roses illustrate this dying 
feudalism in England. When the rival factions had sufficiently 
destroyed each other, Henry Tudor, as Henry VII, backed by 
the urban nonfeudal population, was able to establish monarchy 
in place of feudalism. The English people tolerated, indeed 
heartily supported, this Tudor dynasty in its usurpation of 
absolute power, until feudal claims had become obsolete; yet 
when the people rebelled against royal absolutism, they justified 



the long middle age 


175 

pire with its own government, code of law, and courts. In many 
respects this great ecclesiastical state which crossed ?ill feudd 
boundaries offered to the individual a life more free, more 
inspired, and more humane than might be found elsewhere. It 
was a question, indeed, whether this clerical government might 
not become the sole government of Europe. Yet the church 
itself, since its clergy was celibate, could not be identified with 
European society; and the great expansion of its economic and 
political responsibilities increasingly affected the character of 
the church, secularizing it and prejudicing its religious work. 
Thus the Middle Ages produced a well-nigh insoluble problem, 
a problem that was to convulse Europe in century-long wars 
and that has never ceased to disturb continental Europe. The 
problem was to keep religion authoritative while divesting it of 
secular powers. 

Having brought this problem to an acute stage, the Middle 
Ages came to an end, the feudal and ecclesiastical systems 
crashing down together. Strong kings with the support of their 
commoners usurped the feudal power; the great ecclesiastical 
estates were confiscated and distributed, the clerical orders were 
disbanded. But the deeper problem was not solved by these 
strong-arm measures. Where was now the moral authority, the 
rule of the spirit, which ever since Emperor Constantine’s 
recognition of the church had in theory limited tyrannous 
government? I am that spirit, said the absolute king; I am the 
head and fount of the church. And where was the common law, 
the inborn rights and powers that inhered in some measure in 
every feudal class? I am the law, said the king; all powers derive 
from me. So the fall of feudalism and ecclesiasticism, precip- 
itated by strong Idngs who could sincerely and reasonably 
appeal to the crying need for radical political and economic 
reform, was followed by a period of revolutions, needed to 
establish once again the authority of moral man over established 
power. And we observe that such revolution was successful, 
permanent in its political establishments, and beneficial in its 



the long middle age 177 

early Christianity destroyed or allowed to rot the great libraries 
of later antiquity. That early Christianity prohibited the pagan 
literature is unquestionable; but since this literature was never 
lost in eastern Europe, where the Greek language remained in 
common use, it seems to have been the use of Latin rather than 
any deliberate prohibition that cut western Christianity off 
from Greek science and scholarship. However this may be, 
there is no doubt that the small library of writings which was 
retained by the western church had all the more influence in 
its determination of a distinctively occidental way of thought. 
This library contained the works of Augustine and other Latin 
Fathers in their Latin originals, and also portions of the writings 
of Cicero, Seneca, and Lucretius. In translation from the Greek 
there was of course the New Testament, and also portions of 
the Greek Fathers, a fragment fror the Timaeus of Plato, parts 
of Aristotle’s logic with a commentary by the Neoplatonist 
Porphyry, the Consolations of Boethius, and some philosophical 
commentaries. For some centuries the mind of western Europe 
was whetted on these few texts, which gave to western culture 
a vocabulary, a style of speech, and an orientation of thought 
which are still discernible. Just as a boy today might be better 
educated by the rigorous study of a few well-selected texts than 
by a large amount of casual reading, so it is possible that west- 
ern Europe was blessed and not cursed by its isolation from the 
vast literature of later antiquity. One effect of this isolation 
was that the great systems of Greek science and metaphysics 
became known only when western society had developed itself 
far enough, in exercises logical and theological, to be able to 
meet Greek thought with a measure of independence. So there 
could arise and maintain itself that critical attitude of mind 
which is the chief mark of the western intellect. Our concern 
therefore with these Middle Ages will be the movement to this 
critical attitude of mind, as this movement was stimulated by 
increasing contact with the original thought of Greece. 

The first contact of this kind was a strange one, occurring 



THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 179 

translation of the Greek “idea” or “form.” Porph5n:y in his 
commentary upon Aristotle’s logic had asked: Are universals 
prior to the things which instance them, or in things, or after 
things, Le. in our minds? Roscellinus answered flatly: in our 
minds, and only there, because all actual things are individual 
beings, and there is no being that is not ineradicably individual. 
This is the doctrine of nommalism, which affirms that universal 
or general terms are but names. We can give the same name, 
e.g. “dog,” to any member of a class of similar things; but these 
things are individual beings, and we may not suppose that there 
is some nonindividual sort of being, i.e. universal Being, corre- 
^onding to universal terms. 

This doctrine is at first sight plausible, and we shall see that 
it withstands criticism; yet the nominalist must explain why, 
if general terms refer to nothing real in nature, they are indis- 
pensable to all study and explanation of nature. Does theoretical 
science, which defoes certain very general strucrores such as 
physical structure, chemical structure, etc., describe not a struc- 
ture in nature but only a structure in our minds? The nominal- 
ist will always raise an adversary in the realist, who insists that 
universal terms refer to realities, not to names merely. So 
Anselm of Canterbury, the older and much respected con- 
temporary of Roscellinus, rose to the latter’s challenge with an 
able defense of realistic metaphysics. To deny the reality of 
universal Being, Anselm argued, is to forego all rational knowl- 
edge. To know the tmiversal forms which reside in individual 
things is to understand things. It is to know why things behave 
as they do, and to understand their place and function in the 
universal system of the cosmos. Individual things are therefore 
intelligible and “real” only in virtue of these universal forms 
which they manifest, which forms therefore are most real. It 
is through these universal forms, moreover, that we are led to 
religious truth, since to pursue these causal and formal relations 
is to be led finally to the supreme Form and First Cause of 
everything, which is God. Thus to affirm universals is to afiirm 



THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 


l8l 

modern period, in that it confined itself to book knowledge 
and traditional learning, and did not advance to conclusions 
based upon new evidence reached by original observation and 
experiment. Yet we should do justice to the scholastic method, 
even in recognizing its limitations. It was not subservient, since 
it required the scholar to weigh his textual authorities and to 
depend upon his own judgment. It proposed to advance be- 
yond earlier opinion, by finding in the contradictions of past 
authorities an injunction to independent thought. Scholastic 
method at its best, for example in Abelard or Aquinas, was in 
truth a preparation for modem critical science; and without 
this first stage there could not have developed the second stage. 
In this first stage, the scholar aimed to master past thought, 
accepting its conclusions as evidence yet not as finality, in 
order to reach a higher and truer illumination. Such scholarly 
anal)^, comprehending and weighing all existing knowledge, 
must always form an important part of research. In the second 
stage of th^ development, properly called “science,” the thinker 
turns to observable fact and experiment for new evidence, de- 
rived not from books and past authorities but from nature 
itself. However, a true science will always comprehend the 
insight of the past; and the scholastic method was a proper and 
necessary prelude of the independent natural science of today. 

Abelard’s tragic history is a profound commentary on medie- 
val society. The most brilliant young scholar of his century, 
he could anticipate a clerical career leading to the highest and 
most responsible offices in Europe. This career required 
celibacy; and Abelard fell in love with his lovely and gifted 
pupil Heloise. Heloise, vowing that she would rather be 
Abelard’s mistress than the spouse of an emperor, refused to 
allow her lover to sacrifice his career by regularizing their 
union; and she retired with their daughter to a convent, where 
she wrote those letters which still make this story the most 
authentic and moving of the medieval romances. Abelard, emas- 
culated by the indignant family of Heloise and publicly dis- 



THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 1 83 

read Aristode subserviendy, as if the human reason had uttered 
in Aristode its whole thought and must ever after only think 
that thought again. Yet it was nevertheless Aristode who taught 
Europe to see in nature a great array of natural domains, each 
accessible to the natural light of reason and each delivering its 
appropriate science. And the rebellion against Aristode, neces- 
sary and fruitful as it was, was never able to confine the broad- 
ened mind of Europe to a single narrow discipline. 

It would take too long, nor does it belong within the pur- 
pose of this book, to try to portray the great system of 
Aquinas, which erects upon the flat architectonic of Aris- 
totelian science the towering spire of Christian theology. 
Thoimsm, as we call this system today, became very quickly 
the unofficial, and much later the official, philosophical code 
of the Roman Church, which it remains to this day, when it 
is experiencing a vigorous revival in certain Catholic centers. 
The largest movement of modem science and philosophy, how- 
ever, whatever may be its final or future constitution, has pro- 
ceeded independendy of scholastic thought, and to a consid- 
erable degree in hostile opposition to it. We will note, there- 
fore, only some of the largest and most generally influential 
doctrines of the scholastic philosophy. 

First, Aquinas defined the boundaries and legitimate func- 
tions of faith and reason, i.e. of revealed religion and theoreti- 
cal science. Faith, he taught, reveals the goal toward which 
reason must strive, but which reason cannot of itself attain. 
Because the world is the creation of God’s free and omnipotent 
will, it is a contingent world, i.e. it is a world the character of 
which cannot be deduced from any purely rational premises. 
This principle of the contingency of nature, which Aquinas 
derives from Christian doctrine, is truly the principle which 
calls for an empirical science, reaching its conclusions from 
observed fact, to replace the rationalistic science of antiquity. 
Aquinas concludes further that scientific knowledge must be 
less than complete, because the world, as the creature of an 



THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 1 85 

ml law is the infinite and unknowable will of God. Natural law 
is the part of eternal law accessible to the human reason through 
its scientific study of nature. Divine law is the part revealed to 
man in transmitted religion. Human law is the realization of 
natural and divine law in legal codes, e.g. Roman and canon 
law, and in the jus gentium, the unwritten law regulating 
relations among nations or peoples. By means of this elastic or 
compendious doctrine Aquinas established the concept of a 
divine or natural law, supporting and realized in the actualities 
of government. This was a return to the Greek and Platonic 
ideal of government by law, which Aquinas thus helped to 
make a commonplace of political thought. Aquinas followed 
Aristotle in his conception of the state as a natural outgrowth 
of human sociability. He favored monarchy, as did in the 
thirteenth century most forward-looking thinkers, weary of 
the failures of feudal government. Also forward-looking was 
Aquinas’ doctrine that the state, re^onsible at once to God 
and to the people, must secure the economic welfare of its 
citizens. 

We should see in the scholastic system of Aquinas one of the 
great achievements and emancipating influences of medieval 
thought. It established the authority of a free natural science, 
proceeding from observable fact by way of rational analysis; 
it secured the authority of secular government, yet subjected 
this power to limitations both moral or spiritual and popular 
or legal; and it showed the dependency of both science and 
society upon moral foundations. The later centuries owe much 
to this great and liberal thinker, who combined breadth of 
classical scholarship with mtensity of religious faith. Yet the 
work of Aquinas had very definite limitations, which leave it 
an achievement peculiarly medieval and unmodern. 

Its most obvious limitation was its fidelity to the logic and 
science of Aristotle, whose method, as we noted earlier, consti- 
tuted only one movement of Greek science, and not the most 
fruitful approach to fact. In the hands of men of less genius 



THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 


187 

lay membership of the church testified to the desire of the peo- 
ple of Europe to appropriate to themselves the religious insight 
which earlier had been the prerogative of the ecclesiastical 
priesthood. Very soon, it is true, the Franciscans organized 
themselves into a clerical order similar to that of the Domini- 
cans; and only two centuries later did the Protestant Reforma- 
tion erase in northern Europe the line between the priesthood 
and society at large. But the Franciscan movement foreshad- 
owed, in its unpretentious and simple practice of religion and 
in its philosophical and theological leanings, the modem society 
that issued from the Middle Ages. Franciscan theology looked 
chiefly to Augustine, and gave to the creative thought of that 
great mind an influence greater than it had enjoyed; and the 
memory of St. Francis was preserved in a naturalistic mysticism 
which made the visible world an immediate experience of God. 
Thus BuoTiaventara, a contemporary of Aquinas and the first 
Franciscan philosopher, tells us to see in our immediate experi- 
ence the small analogue of the universal and divine process by 
which God creates the world. Earlier theology had looked to 
the authority of tradition, derived from revelation in the past; 
but St. Francis, in the power of his direct experience of God, 
taught his followers a new way of truth, a new confidence in 
their powers of immediate apprehension, and a new concep- 
tion of that ultimate Being which is at every time accessible to 
the earnest and illuminated mind. Following the lives and 
words of these thirteenth-century Franciscans, we feel that we 
are attending the birth of a new mentality, one that is modem, 
democratic, and empirical; and we are not surprised to dis- 
cover in the writings of certain Franciscan scholars the initial 
steps of the science and philosophy of today. This modem way 
of thought we call “empirical” or “empiricistic,” because it 
emphasizes experience rather than reason, even at the expense 
of reason. By “experience” is meant the immediate perception 
of sensible fact, and by “reason,” in this context, is meant the 
conceptual formulations and explicit theories of the intellect. 



THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 


189 

whole business of science, he said, is to know clearly the small 
set of primary and universal principles basic to mathematical 
science, and to apply these principles, directly or through ex- 
perimentation, to the observable phenomena of nature, which 
wiU everywhere reveal their perfect fidelity to mathematical 
pattern. He mercilessly castigated the loose and haphazard 
“learning” of his time, and was especially critical of Aristotelian 
science. He professed adherence to the established religion; but 
he called upon the church to cast out its unscientific philosophy, 
and to encourage this mathematical and experimental research. 
It is the virtue of this true science, he said, to give man power 
over nature; and this great instrument, if the church neglects 
its use, will fall into the hands of the enemies of the church 
and be used to destroy the church. The church did not respond 
to these vehement exhortations. It imprisoned the hot old 
genius during the last decade or more of his long life, none 
other than the saintly and gifted Buenaventura signing the 
order for his incarceration; and we shall never know what the 
church might have become if instead of repudiating its great 
son it had united the development of modern science with its 
own religious aspiration, and not required posterity to choose 
between scientific truth and religious orthodoxy. 

The complete teaching of Roger Bacon is a matter of some 
obscurity. Only fragments of his writings are preserved, some 
of his works being inscribed in a curious cipher not yet de- 
coded. But it is established that he was a great initiator of ex- 
perimental theoretical science, looking to experience and at- 
tempting an independent analysis of observed fact. He seems to 
have united the mathematical faith of Plato with the new Fran- 
ciscan and Augustinian insight into the potentialities of our 
immediate experience of nature. Just how Bacon united reason 
and experience we do not know; but that he did bring them to- 
gether into a most fruitful union is shown by the long develop- 
ment of science and philosophy, reaching down to ourselves, 
which issued from him. In Bacon first was the great impetus of 



THE LONG MIDDLE AGE 


I9I 

are, Occam taught, two criteria or tests of knowledge, not 
merely one. The first is the rational criterion — our conclusions 
must be deducible from basic self-evident principles, such as 
the axioms of mathematics. The second is the empirical cri- 
terion, which requires that general knowledge must confirm 
itself in all observable particular fact. We saw how Eriugena 
in the ninth century fost set forth this double requirement, 
which Occam in the fourteenth century restates in clearer 
language. It is this double requirement that distinguishes mod- 
em empirical science from all earlier science, which was ration- 
alistic because it emphasized the first requirement to the neglect 
of the second. We must believe that Occam publicized in this 
way the scientific theory and practice proposed by his prede- 
cessor Roger Bacon. This means that modem science was in- 
augurated in its essential principles in the thirteenth century. 

Equally important for the rise of empirical science was a 
second doctrine promulgated by Occam. The objective of 
science, he taught, is the discovery of causal relations among 
particular things. Medieval learning, following Aristotle, had 
found the causes of individual things in their specific forms, 
i.e. in the conformity of particular fact to general forms, which 
constitute in this view the general causes of particular events. 
(So today we might explain the motion of the moon as a par- 
ticular instance of the general “law” of gravitation.) In a slash- 
ing attack upon the scholastic science, Occam rejected this 
sort of explanation as merely verbal. To classify a thing as a 
member of a certain species, or to classify an event as a certain 
sort of event or as the instance of some law, does not inform 
us concerning the cause of that thing or that event. The causes 
of a particular thing or event lie in other particular things or 
events. (Thus although we say that the motion of the moon 
is an instance of the law of gravitation, we mean that the 
moon is determined in its motion by the action upon it of 
particular forces exerted by particular bodies, chiefly the earth 
and sun.) There are in every occurrence or change, it follows, 



raE LONG MIDDLE AGE 


193 

must be something in individual things which corresponds to 
the general formula and is truly indicated by it. But we forgive 
Occam’s error because of the value and truth of his positive 
account of science. Occam’s strictures upon scientific method 
became a deathblow to all forms of scholastic, merely ration- 
alistic science, and the foundation of an empirical science 
which derives its hypotheses from experienced fact and con- 
firms them again therein. 

We have given considerably more space and importance to 
these medieval Franciscans than is usually accorded to them. 
Our purpose is to correct the stiU prevalent superstition 
that modern science suddenly appeared, without notable 
antecedents, at the time of the Renaissance. We must insist that 
modem science in its distinctive character was initiated by these 
clerics working in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries. 
What was the deep and obscure feeling which motivated these 
men, whose thought was to transform the human intellecj:,‘and 
through this the human world.? What compelled them to rebel 
against all the scientific and philosophic^ authority of the 
past? What insight gave them their moral courage and their 
scientific power? In their own day, remember, they could ap- 
peal to no great body of empirical achievement such as exists 
today. For their scientific experiments they were suspect in the 
public eye, as devotees of the “black art” of magic. For their 
philosophical teachings they were persecuted, ostracized, 
despised by their learned fellows. Bacon languished in prison; 
and the name of Duns Scotus became the scornful epithet 
dunce,” hurled by orthodox scholars at these subversive non- 
conformists. Did these followers of St. Francis see a new world 
because they strained toward a new society, a society emanci- 
pated from the political bonds of feudalism and the intellectual 
bonds of medieval ecclesiasticism? Was their intellectual rebel- 
lion the van of a social and religious rebellion? The early 
Greeks established Greek science because they insisted that 
nature, like Greek society, must manifest a legal constitution, 



IHE LONG MIDDLE AGE X95 

8. The Classical Heritage of the Middle Ages. New York, 

The Macmillan Company, 1923. 

9. Crump, C. G,, and Jacob, E. F., The Legacy of the Middle 

Ages, Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1943, Oxford Series. 

10. Coker, F. W., Readings in folitical Philosophy. New York, 
The Macmillan Company, 1938, Chap. V. 

II* Mcllwain, C. H., The Growth of Political Thought in the 
West. New York, The Macmillan Company, 1932, Chap, V. 



THE BIRTH OF MODERN SOCIETY 


197 

democratic government must have consequences in the do- 
mestic, educational, recreational, social, and religious activities 
of a people. 

While it is proper to describe modern society in terms of 
these distinctive political and social institutions, the word 
“modem” indicates a direction of social evolution rather than 
any set of fixed institutions. The American colonies were evi- 
dently moving toward democratic government; yet they still 
retained much that was undemocratic and old-world. Democ- 
racy is a direction of thought and life. It is a movement that 
began some centuries ago, and that will indefinitely continue 
its transformation of social institutions and human character. 

Between this modem movement to democracy and medieval 
feudalism occurred a transitional period marked by monarchi- 
cal government. The rapid breakdown of feudal institutions 
under the stress of new conditions made a temporary dictator- 
ship inevitable. Monarchies were established wherever some 
able and ambitious feudal lord, supported by a public seeking 
escape from feudal forms, was able to enlarge his feudal ofiice 
into that of sovereign. In this way developed nations, or socie- 
ties centrally organized around the monarch, in whose person 
was centered and symbolized the national unity. England best 
illustrates this transition from feudalism to a more modem form 
of government. Henry VII ended the destractive wars be- 
tween feudal factions, established royal power, carried through 
legal and economic reforms, prevented the recovery of the 
feudal nobility, and encouraged the development of national 
industry and commerce. He and his Tudor successors exercised 
virtually absolute powers, which they owed to their able and 
firm government and to their encouragement of commercial 
and urban interests which had found no place in the feudal 
system. The English parliament, a representative but still feudal 
institution, could not prevent this monarchical assumption of 
power; but it kept alive the memory of feudal rights, and never 
acquiesced in the theory and practice of absolute monarchy. 



the birth of modern SOCIETy 199 

movement to democratic government, was that of religious 
freedom. The Stuarts had long resisted the Presbyterian Scotch, 
who wished to retain the management of the church in their 
own hands. Finally, when the Presbyterians threw out his ap- 
pointees, Charles I summoned the J^glish parliament to vote 
him monies to suppress these rebels. Parliament, itself mainly 
Presbyterian, voted instead to support the rebels, and declared 
war against Charles. The parliamentary armies were largely 
composed of Puritan dissenters officered by Presbyterian gen- 
try; and when parliament moved to make terms with Charles, 
these soldiers took power into their own hands, set up a tribunal 
which tried and executed Charles on the charge of high treason, 
and established the Commonwealth, a form of government 
which was neither monarchical nor parliamentary. 

This English revolution established the political principle 
of the supremacy of law. Charles I, who had claimed to be 
above the law, was executed for breaking the law. It is often 
forgotten that this revolution also proceeded to the establish- 
ment of a republican form of government, enabling a people 
to rule itself directly through its moral and religious leaders. 
Since the Stuarts had alienated almost every section of society, 
the revolution against them was variously motivated, economi- 
cally, socially, and politically, as well as religiously; but it 
is impossible to mistake the dominantly religious origin, motiva- 
tion, and outcome of this first of all the revolutions that have 
modernized society. The British people, having rejected the 
authority of Rome and subjected themselves to a Puritan 
discipline of their own making, proposed now to preserve this 
religious and moral power from royal interference, and to make 
of it the ruler of their land. It was a Puritan revolution, issuing 
in a Puritan government. 

To be convinced of the moral and religious motivation which 
impelled the movement to modem democratic society, one 
must observe that only where the movement of Puritan reform 
was able to advance with relative freedom did the movement 



the birth of modern society 


201 


much. There, as earlier in Tudor England, the established 
clergy sided with the national monarch in his struggle against 
papal authority; but they later required, as recompense for this 
support, his persecution of the reformed religion. Here, too, 
the consequence of the Reformation was to identify an estab- 
lished church with a royalist and absolutistic form of govern- 
ment; and the struggle for political liberty became anticlerical, 
and in its theory atheistic. The French revolution was accord- 
ingly long delayed and unusually bloody and bitter, and the 
republic which it established was never stable. This has been the 
history of every libertarian movement which was not sup- 
ported and strengthened by free religion. 

The seventeenth century was remarkable for its production 
of political pamphlets. This literature was an outgrowth of the 
religious and theological literature, also tremendous in bulk, 
which had followed the Reformation. After the failure of the 
Commonwealth with its Puritan objectives the liberal thinker 
turned increasingly to philosophical and moral principles in his 
efFort to substantiate his political purposes. The political theory 
developed during the later seventeenth century was the chief 
instruction of those who gave to modem society its political 
constitution; and among these political theorists one name, that 
of John Locke, outranks all the rest. 

The purpose of the creators of modem government was to 
enfranchise and empower the individual conscience, by making 
effective in every individual his religious responsibility for all 
of his fellows. This responsibility, it was now clear, could be 
fully exercised only through a control of government. Yet 
how could the freedom and power of the individual be recon- 
ciled with the fact of government? How may law, with its 
restriction upon individual behavior, leave unimpaired the 
moral power of the individual? 

During the Middle Ages this crucial problem had been par- 
tially solved by a division of the governing power among feudal 
ranks and between church and state. The degree and kind of 



IHE BIRTH OF MODERN SOCIETY 


203 

and solidly organized people, defined in terms of their posses- 
sion of territory and their political unity. The nonmoral char- 
acter of this “realistic” political theory is starkly apparent in 
its two best-known exponents, Machiavelli and Hobbes. 

Machiavelli, a Florentine who wrote early in the sixteenth 
century, was inspired by his too idealistic conception of 
ancient Rome. He dreamed of a strong and united Italy, and 
looked enviously toward France and England, which had al- 
ready achieved national solidarity. Several causes had kept 
Italy divided into warring principalities, the chief cause, 
Machiavelli believed, being the concern of the Papacy to keep 
intact its papal domains. What Italy needed, he concluded, was 
a prince whose personal ambition would override all religious 
and other scruples, and whose skill in intrigue and war would 
enable him to unify Italy by sheer force. In his famous book 
The Trince he presented a manual of advice and instruction for 
such a tyrant. Machiavelli was a genuine patriot, weary of the 
political turmoil and the moral corruption which he saw about 
him; and at heart he was a liberal, one who would revive the 
virtues of stout and honest citizenship as they had supposedly 
existed in republican Rome. He assumed, however, that th^ 
patriotic purpose justified, every intrigue, deceit, and violence. 
He calls for a ruler whose power over his people is absolute, 
and who will use education and religion to keep his subjects 
devoted to himself and to his political ambition. Machiavelli’s 
book, full of sincere, shrewd, yet cynical perception of the 
baser motives playing into political life, has been for four cen- 
turies the guide of unscrupulous statesmen, until its essential 
doctrine, teaching that the state as the whole source of law and 
right transcends moral limitations, became the creed of a new 
tyranny in Mussolini, Franco, and Hitler. 

More than a century after Machiavelli, this doctrine of politi- 
cal absolutism was given systematic expression by Thomas 
Hobbes in his book Tevtathan, still regarded as a classical work 
because of its bold effort to deal realistically with the forces 



THE BIRTH OF MODERN SOCIETr 


205! 

equally manifest one and the same law which is thai,,^ uni- 
versal and divine justice, Hobbes defines the individual aii^ the 
state in such a way as to make their reconciliation impossible. 
The individual is defined as in his inherent and constitutive 
nature lawless, wholly belligerent, and nonmoral; and the 
state thus becomes something superhuman, imposed upon the 
individual by an external and alien power. Hobbes did not hesi- 
tate to call the monarch “a mortal god.” His theory is close 
to that of the Greek sophists, who held all law to be nothing 
but artificial convention, without real authority and imposed 
by force or deceit. The concepts of natural rights and natural 
law have never wholly recovered from this Hobhesian in- 
terpretation. 

Hobbes’ intention, of course, was to justify political author- 
ity as the true law, that of reason and morality; but he defined 
the individual in such a way as to allow no relationship be- 
tween individual freedom and rational or moral law. Law must 
be imposed upon the individual from without, by an external 
force. To jus^y and explain this imposition, Hobbes gave to 
another curnent idea, that which held government to arise out 
of a contract, a new and strange interpretation. The Epi- 
cureans, it may be recalled, had used this contract theory to 
deny moral authority to the slate. The state is in the position 
of a contractor, they held, commissioned by society to perform 
certain specified and limited functions. Hobbes, however, 
describes a strange contract according to which the individuals 
composing society irrevocably renounce aU their inherent 
powers, and place these without residue in the hands of the 
sovereign, who undertakes in return to make the good of the 
state identical with his own good, to maintain law and order, 
and to delegate to his subjects only such powers as will not 
disturb the common peace. This implies that all real individual 
rights, as distinguished from those “natural rights” which ac- 
cording to Hobbes are just lawless powers, derive from the 
state or the monarch; and this is the constitutive principle of 



THE BERTH OF MODERN SOaETY 


207 

was generally conceived to establish the principle of self- 
government. In the writings of its spokesman Locke, indeed, 
this revolution produced the classical exposition of democratic 
theory. 

Jolm Locke, son of a small landholder whose services in the 
first revolution had depleted his fortune, qualified himself as a 
physician, but remained at Oxford pursuing scientific and 
scholarly research until his close relations with certain Whig 
noblemen caused the Stuart monarch to demand his dismissal. 
Locke went to Holland, where with other conspirators he 
prepared the way for the Whig revolution. Following his 
return to England with the new monarch, he published in rapid 
succession the political and philosophical works which he had 
prepared in exile. 

Since the Stuarts and their supporters defended absolute 
monarchy on the principle of the divine right of the king, 
Locke directed his chief attack against this doctrine, and not 
against the more systematic theory of absolute government 
presented by Hobbes; but the positive argument of Locke con- 
stitutes a criticism and correction of Hobbes’ theory. Rebut- 
ting the doctrine of divine right on its own ground, that of 
scriptural interpretation, he offers a defense of self-government 
which is independent of religious premises. 

Starting as did Hobbes from the concept of the self-deter- 
minate individual, Locke immediately diverges from Hobbes in 
his conception of the individual, whom be finds to be naturally, 
prior to dl government, bound to his fellows in moral associa- 
tion. Thus the initial concept of Locke is really that of a society 
or moral community, composed of free individuals who are 
bound to one another by reciprocal friendship and concern. 
This moral individualism of Locke is often confused -with the 
nonmoral individualism of Hobbes and others; but this con- 
fusion leaves Locke’s political philosophy quite unintelligible 
I and robs his theory of all moral basis. The initial principle of 
democracy places aU moral responsibility in the individual per- 



THE BERTH OF MODERN SOCIETY 


209 

rion of this theory, as it must be the intention of any theory 
which proposes to invalidate absolute government, to deny 
intrinsic authority to the state, and to locate all authority and 
all ultimate power in the people, which is conceived to be inde- 
pendent of the state, to be prior to the state, and to outlast the 
state. 

The foundation of this theory is its affirmation of the good- 
ness of the individual human being. Only if man is moral can 
he be worthy or capable of self-government. This does not 
mean that man is always and everywhere incapable of evil. It 
means that man is essentially or generally good; above all, it 
means that no line can divide people into two species of beings, 
one good and therefore worthy of exercising government, the 
other bad and therefore unworthy to govern. If men axe gen- 
erally good, and all men govern, government will be generally 
good. But the goodness of man lies finally in his free moral will. 
It is because man is a free moral agent, able to know and choose 
between good and evil, that he is invested with inalienable 
authority. No individual and no group of individuals has the 
right to deny to another individual or group of individuals the 
exercise of moral judgment and power. Democracy is the only 
form of government which does not at some point deny this 
conception of the moral nature of man. 

Since all authority or right whatsoever inheres in the human 
individual, one cannot exhaustively list the “rights of man.” 
Locke emphasized especially, as natural rights which require a 
specific limitation of governmental power, the rights of reli- 
gion freedom and of property. It should be obvious that an 
individual can delegate to no one else his religious responsi- 
bilities; and just government may accordingly exercise no 
authority of any sort over religious belief. Locke extended this 
requirement of religious toleration to all save Romanists, who, 
he believed, were by their allegiance to Rome compelled to 
deny toleration to others, and thus prevented from entPitiTig r 
into the compact establishing free government. 



the birth of modern society 21 1 

therefore, of the right of a people to regulate through its gov- 
ernment its economic life. "V^y, therefore, should there be any 
limit to the extent of this economic regulation? If government 
is controlled by the people, should not the people through its 
government exert complete and absolute economic control? 

To answer this question intelligently, we should observe that 
every sort of control exercised in human society is either 
directly economic, or dependent upon economic means. This is 
true of the control exerted by a people upon its government, 
as well as that exerted through its government. Laws are not 
effective until they are administered; and the administration 
of law is effected and controlled by means of monetary appro- 
priations. It is not enough, in order to know the political form 
of a society, to know its written constitution. The written 
constitution may appear to be democratic, yet leave govern- 
ment autocratic. The constitution is effective only if it is mate- 
rially implemented. But we learn the political form’ of a society 
unmistakably when we discover the sources and controls of the 
monies and other economic powers at the disposal of its govern- 
ment. 

Thus a government not dependent upon appropriations, 
ultimately derived from taxes voted freely by property owners, 
may hire an army which makes it independent of every con- 
trol — except, perhaps, that exerted upon government by the 
army itself. Governments are in the last resort groups of men; 
and to place in the hands of any group of men complete con- 
trol of the national economy will automatically place those 
men beyond popular control. This is not only a theoretical 
deduction. It is also a generalization from facts which have 
always been apparent. There are countries today in which such 
complete economic control not only makes government com- 
pletely independent of public opinion, but places it beyond the 
threat of popular revolution. Thus the proposal to secure to the 
people complete control of its economic life by means of gov- 
ernment ownership, or unlimited governmental power over 



THE BIRTH OF MODERN SOCIETY 


213 

private ownership, Locke also provided the means which 
would preserve this principle from abuse. He did this by defin- 
ing property as the product of labor. Locke meant, of course, 
every sort of labor, and did not narrow the term, as we unfor- 
tunately narrow it, to specify only certain types of economic 
activity. This principle, taken in its whole meaning, provides a 
basis for broad legislation securing to all individuals that eco- 
nomic justice which is in fact, most would agree, a condition as 
well as an objective of democratic practice. 

Locke’s political philosophy gets its full weight only when 
it is placed in the context of his general philosophy, which we 
will consider in a later chapter; but it constitutes as it stands 
the classical exposition of democratic political theory, and the 
basis upon which was erected and still is established the con- 
stitutional democracy of today. The theory is not affected by 
any criticism of the concepts of “natural law” and “natural 
rights,” in terms of which Locke presented it. This language, 
appropriate to Locke’s time, only denoted the facts of moral 
responsibility and moral community which every adequate 
social and political theory must recognize. There are really 
only two kinds of political theory and practice. There is demo- 
cratic theory and practice, which places moral authority in the 
individual human being and derives all governmental powers 
and social values from this; and there is absolutistic theory and 
practice, or the “philosophy of the state,” which ostensibly 
locates authority and value in some institution, but really 
locates it in some hereditary or self-appointed group of indi- 
viduals, identified with the state. 

Democracy is not one of a number of political forms, among 
which we may choose that most appropriate to present circum- 
stance. Democracy cannot afford to be relativistic. Democracy 
is the acknowledgment in theory and practice of the fact 
of individuality, which fact is the source of all natural moral 
law. As we shall see later, democracy is the practical applica- 
tion in human relations of those selfsame principles winch in 



THE BIRTH OF MODERN SOCIETY 


215 

preciation of the development of modern science, allowing us 
to understand its method and to grasp its presuppositions. This 
study, which we begin in the following chapter, will be our 
concern to the end of the book. Just as Greek philosophy was 
a reflection upon Greek science, so modem philosophy has 
been a reflection upon the methods and results of modern 
science, especially in their implications for social and political 
life. 


Notes for Further Reading 

1. Sabine, G. H., A History of Political Theory. New York, 

Henry Holt and Company, Chaps. XVIl-XXVI, 1937. 

2. Figgis, J. N., “Political Thought in the Sixteenth Century.’' 

Cambridge Modem History ^ New York, The Macmillan 
Company, 1904, Vol. Ill, Chap. 22. 

3. Smith, P., The Age of the Reformation. New York, Henry 

Holt and Company, 1920. 

4. Machiavelli, N., The Prince. Chicago, Packard and Company, 

1941, also various editions. 

5. Lanquet, H., A Defense of Liberty against Tyrants^ introd. by 

H. J. Laski, New York, Harcourt Brace and Company, Inc., 
1924. 

6. Laski, H. J., “The Rise of Liberalism.” Encyclopaedia of the 

Social Sciences. New York, The Macmillan Company, 1930, 
VoL 1 . 

7. Gooch, G. P., English Democratic Ideas in the Seventeenth 

Century. New York, The Macmillan Company, 1927. 

8. Laird, J., Hobbes. London and New York, Oxford University 

Press, 1934. 

9. Hobbes, T,, Leviathan. Garden City, Doubleday Doran and 

Company, 1937, Parts I and IL 

10. Smith, A. L., “English Political Philosophy in the Seventeenth 

and Eighteenth Centuries,” Cambridge Modern History^ 
New York, The Macmillan Company, 1909, Vol. VI. 

11. Laski, H. J., Political Thought in England from Locke to 

Bentham. New York, Henry Holt and Company, 1920. 

12. Lamprecht, S., The Moral and Political Philosophy of John 

Locke. New York, Columbia University Press, Archives of 
Philosophy, No. ii, 1918. 



THE RISE OR MODERN SCIENCE iI7 

and primarily it was an exodus out of the cloister, into the 
several vernaculars of western Europe, of the Latin learning 
of the medieval clerics. It was also a recovery and temporary 
adoration of the classical and pagan cultures of antiquity. But 
finally and most importantly it was the expression of a new 
outlook upon nature and man, a new attitude toward fact, 
and a new enterprise of the human spirit. This new mind 
eludes definition, but we can perceive and indicate its most 
important features. 

First, perhaps, we should note its great swing to an orienta- 
tion upon the future, after centuries intellectually focused 
upon the past. Out of this reorientation was bom the most 
dynamic and creative as well as the most revolutionary and 
turbulent force in the modem world, to wit the concept of 
progress. The new vista upon an unlimited human progress is 
perhaps the deepest meaning of the phrases, such as the Renais- 
sance, the Enlightenment, and the Age of Reason, which men 
coined to express their satisfaction with and their confidence in 
the new prospect. This concept of progress was incorporated 
into and supported by the new science. Greek science, and 
after it medieval science, had conceived of a completed wis- 
dom, progressive perhaps in its application to new situations 
and problems, but essentially static and whole. Socrates had 
not been able to convert men to his conception of science as a 
pursuit of knowledge, something at once less and more than the 
possession of knowledge; but modem science has conceived 
itself to be a progressive exploration of nature rather t han a 
final statement of eternal and fixed truth. With this increas- 
ing faith in a progressive science has come new faith in the 
contmuous improvement of human nature and the conditions 
of human life. We find the distant origins of this new faith in 
the gospel of hope and deliverance announced by early Chris- 
tianity. Medieval Christianity had fixated Christian faith upon 
a supernatural and otherworldly goal, to be attained only after 
death; but the Reformation, returning to earliest Christianity 



THE RISE OF MODERN SaENCE 


219 

The earlier poems and comedies of Shakespeare we may dis- 
miss, since they illustrate chiefly the superficial neoclassicism 
which is sometimes still identified with the Renaissance, but 
which was truly only its accident. In this neoclassical art the 
artist tried, impossibly, to re-create the thought and imagina- 
tion of Greek antiquity; and he succeeded only in appropriat- 
ing the archaic mythology and the external conventions of 
antique art, grasping nothing of the antique spirit. He remained 
still a fifteenth- or sixteenth-century European, rather ludi- 
crously cavorting in tunic or toga. 

The historical plays of Shakespeare, however, already boldly 
innovate the realism of modem art. If these plays are read in 
the chronological order of their events, they will be found to 
constitute a single drama of epical dimensions, telling of the 
curse with its fatal repercussions which was the War of the 
Roses, the curse being lifted and the bloody sequence ended 
through the accession of Henry Tudor. The theme is remini- 
scent of the great trilogy of Aeschylus; and Shakespeare’s new 
realism appears in this, that where the Greek poet took his 
theme from mythology, Shakespeare made use of not so distant 
history to portray the working of natural and moral law. Here 
in modem art, as in modem science, is a subordination of 
imagination to historical and particular fact. 

But it was in his tragedies, and especially in Hamlet, that 
Shakespeare reached that mental and moral crisis out of which 
sprang his supremest art, revealing his full and still immeasur- 
able stature. In the earlier tragedies he had still conformed to 
the medieval roster of virtues and vices. Othello is jealousy, 
Coriolanus and Caesar are ambition, Macbeth is vacillation, 
Lear is vanity masked by paternal fondness. But in Ha?nlet, 
Shakespeare calls into question the moral foundations of the 
universe. That unusual impartiality, with which in the earlier 
dramas both heroes and villains are sympathetically understood, 
now becomes the center of the play. 

It is customary to call Hamlet a work so profound as to be 



THE RISE OF MODERN SCIENCE 


221 


philosophy- and ethics of the last three centuries. It is not an 
irreligious, still less is it an immoral naturalism; but it is religion 
and morality without dogma, in pursuit of widening vision and 
creative power. 

The intellectual revolution and inauguration which genius 
such as that of Shakespeare and Buonarroti announced in art 
had its theoretical parallel in science. To the Pole fan Kopemik 
(1473-1543) we credit the “Copemican revolution” which 
was so much more than an astronomical hypothesis afBrming 
the revolution of the earth about the sun. Why did the Coper- 
nican theory arouse such dissension, such ardent support and 
resolute opposition, that intellectual Europe was divided by it 
into two belligerent camps? From the viewpoint of today, the 
Copemican astronomy only further applied the scientific 
method initiated by the Pythagoreans, and cultivated in some 
measure throughout the intervening ages. Strictly speaking, 
this solar-centric astronomy constituted only an appropriation 
of Greek science, with its commitment to mathematical prin- 
ciples and celestial spheres. Copernicus gave to the circular mo- 
tions a new center in the sun; but this had been proposed by 
Aristarchus of Samos shortly after 300 B.a; and we find that 
Copernicus gave due credit to his Pythagorean sources. Yet 
this Copemican hypothesis shocked western Europe out of its 
dogmatic slumber, by requiring a new and strange conception 
of the world. It returned, after centuries of Aristotle and 
Aristotelianized Platonism, to the mathematical methods of 
Pythagoras and Plato himself, ignoring and discrediting the 
Aristotelian science which was now the basis of scholastic 
theology and the content of scholastic learning. 

Secondly, because the work of Aristarchus had been neg- 
lected and forgotten, the h3q)othesis appeared as a bold and 
independent advance going beyond all earlier achievement; 
and thus it established the intellectual parity of living man 
with antiquity, or even his intellectual superiority. For seven- 
teen or more centuries the conclusions of fourth-century 



THE RISE or MODERN SCIENCE 22} 

they worked steadily and creatively, in England and later in 
France, to produce the discipline which has developed into 
modem physical science. After Occam, who directed the 
new science on its way, we find Nicholas d’Autricourt apply- 
ing atomistic concepts, to facilitate the reduction of particular 
causal sequences to measurable and mathematically formulable 
displacements. John Buridan fashioned the fruitful concept of 
impetus or momentum. Albert of Saxony defined the center of 
gravity of a body and the principle of gravitational accelera- 
tion. And Nicholas Oresmus elaborated the mathematical cal- 
culi which made possible the applications of these concepts to 
particular physical situations. These and other medieval 
thinkers, most of them Franciscan clerics, created the terrestrial 
physics which in the hands of Newton was to be mightily 
enlarged, to swallow up the celestial astronomy of Copernicus 
and Kepler, and to establish the universal yet empirical study 
of fact which is modem science. 

During the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, however, the 
new science emerged from the cloister, and was much stimu- 
lated by its application to secular and practical uses. Navigators 
looked to it for new instruments and for a new cartography. 
Builders of ships, docks, and canals encouraged inquiry into 
the principles of hydrostatics, discovering the stresses exerted 
in and by fluids. There was considerable invention of simple 
machinery applying mechanical principles, and a great devel- 
opment of mining and metallurgy, often scientifically directed. 
Merchants encouraged the invention of new methods of cal- 
culation and bookkeeping. It was a great age, holding in 
embryo the industrial world which was to come. Most notable 
of these practical interests encouraging science, it must be con- 
fessed, was the desire for new arts of war, which stimulated 
Galileo’s study of the morion of projectiles. 

Galileo Galilei of Pisa (1564—1642) owes his popular fame 
to his confirmation of the Copemican theory, and to his adher- 
ence to this hypothesis in face of ecclesiastical opposition. Sum- 



THE RISE OF MODERN SCIENCE 


225 

The principle of gravitation states that material bodies will at- 
tract one another according to the product of their masses and 
the inverse square of their distance. Why attract, and not 
repel? 'Why attract according to the product and not the sum 
of the masses? Why the inverse square, rather than the inverse 
cube, of their distances? There is no answer to these questions, 
except the answer that this is the way in which material bodies 
observ'ably behave. The principle, in short, is inductive, not 
rational — ^it is a summary of particular observations, not the 
deliverance of a prescient reason. Newton, as a matter of fact, 
entertained many alternative and equally reasonable hypo- 
theses, before he discovered that which exactly conformed to 
his data. 

If we will keep steadily before our minds this character of 
the principle of gravitation, a principle at once umversd yet 
inductive or empirical, we shall follow with understanding the 
whole later development of modem thought. The significance 
of this principle is its implied teaching that the whole character 
of nature, even its largest, most ultimate, and most basic char- 
acter, is to be known by observation and in no other way. 
Modem science accepts this implication. We therefore call it 
“empirical science,” indicating in this way that its conclusions 
are derived wholly from sense-experience. Because Greek and 
medieval science believed the largest principles of knowledge 
to be established by reason alone, and to be applied to experi- 
ence and imposed upon experience by the reason, we properly 
call that earlier science “rational” and “nonempirical.” 

Newton may properly be regarded, therefore, as the chief 
founder of modem science. In the principle of gravitation he 
confirmed and securely established the science which his pred- 
ecessors, from Grosseteste and Roger Bacon onward, had 
initiated. The later seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries 
dimly felt this peculiar importance of Newton’s science. They 
saw in Newton the great frontispiece of a new “age of reason,” 
and the source of a new “enlightenment.” 



THE RISE OF M(»ERN SCIENCE 227 

genuinely empirical, we see; yet it still confused inductive 
knowledge, reached by observation, with rational principles 
supposedly inherent in the mind prior to experience. Was it 
materialistic, or Platonic.!’ It was Platonic in its mathematical 
approach and in its mathematical anatomy; but did it not seek 
to explain everything as a consequence of the motions, distribu- 
tions, and inertias of material particles? In a sense it did; but it 
recognized also the two infinite media of space and time, which 
support and condition all this mechanical occurrence; and space 
and time seem to be immaterial. But are space and time effec- 
tive? Are not space and time just passive conditions, necessary 
to but in no way determining mechanical occurrence? Newton 
himself spoke of space as the sensorium of God, meaning that 
it functions as a divine .medium conditioning everytlung that 
happens, but affecting everything equally, so that its effect 
cannot be measured and may be canceled out of our calcula- 
tions. Today the physicist inclines to believe that space is effec- 
tive, and that it conations material motion variously and there- 
fore calculably; but he is also inclined to explain the character 
of space at any place as determined by matter at or near that 
place, and this is again a materialistic view. Today we are 
aware of radiant energies such as light, which do not conform 
to the formulas applicable to solid matter; but Newton, who 
developed this science of light, conceived light to be made up 
of material corpuscles; and contemporary science now con- 
ceives of the transmutability of radiant energy and matter. 

We should conclude, perhaps, that the Newtonian science 
was materialistic, but that it raised the question of the relation 
between the material constituents of nature and the fixed 
“laws” or principles which these constituents seem to obey in 
all of their motions. The question is whether the universal 
principles are determined by the material motions, or the mate- 
rial motions determined by the universal principles. The seven- 
teenth century was apt to answer this question unhesitatingly,, 
uncritically, and piously. The principles were taken to be the 



THE RISE OF MOTERN SCIENCE 


229 

tively perpetuates itself in the individual uniqueness of things? 

Unfortunately these questions have never been put with 
sufficient clearness by later philosophy. Two habits of mind 
have worked to prevent a clear discernment of the problem, 
as it is perpetuated in modified form in modem science- The 
first of these habits is just the Greek and medieval philosophy 
itself. Where the thinker did not clearly perceive the differ- 
ence between modem science and earlier science, namely its 
departure from the Greek dualism, he did not give up the now 
obsolete concepts of form- and matter, but tried confusedly to 
make use of them in estimating the results of modem science. 
The second obstractive habit of mind was that established by 
the medieval nominalists. Why not say, said the nominalists, 
that particulars alone are real, and that universal forms are 
just mental fictions, resident only in the mind? This easy dis- 
position of the problem still appeals to overspecialized and 
myopic minds. Why not suppose, these contemporary nom- 
inalists say, that our scientific theories are only useful mental 
constracts, facilitating the recall or anticipation of particular 
sense impressions? Suppose we do say this — ^have we solved our 
problem? Do not these mental constracts still function as uni- 
versals, whenever we use them in relation to particular sense- 
experience? And do they not exist in ourselves? We do not 
solve the problem of universal knowledge by confining uni- 
versals to the mind. We only renounce all hope of solving the 
problem, or forbid its discussion. The real problem is still 
where it was for the Greeks, in the world and not in the mind. 
To know how and why we can have a general knowledge of 
facts which in themselves are wholly particularized, we must 
know how and why particular things or particular events con- 
form, or at least seem to conform, to general and universal 
principles. Why are things so amilar, and similar in just such 
and such ways? 

The result especially of this second habit of min d was to 
convert a real and genuinely scientific problem, namely the 



the rise of modern science 231 

Plato pointed in the right empirical direction when he in- 
structed his students to “save the appearances,” i.e. to work 
toward the closest conformity of hypothesis to observed fact; 
but modem science is not concerned merely to save the ap- 
pearances— it makes the appearances its whole criterion of 
truth. Modem science is hard put to save the theory. Modern 
science is faithful to Plato in its pursuit of theoretical knowl- 
edge, mathematically formulated; but it conjoins with the 
Platonic rationalism, first, Aristotle’s identification of real being 
with individual being or particular fact; and second, the Greek 
atomist’s denial of chance, his insistence on complete causal 
determinism. Nothing in intellectual history is so astonishing, 
so strange, so disturbing, and also so pregnant, as the successful 
union in modem science of principles which to earlier thought 
seemed irreconcilably incompatible, and which to many eradite 
minds seem so still. 

Notice finally that the new science, at least in its Newtonian 
form, comprised a great philosophy or metaphysic. It postu- 
lated the reality of ultimate material particles, moving in the 
independent and infinite media of space and time, and causally 
influencing one another according to a definable set of uni- 
versally effective principles. So universal and comprehensive 
a conception constitutes a philosophy, a metaphysical system. 
We can, of course, proceed to further philosophical discussion 
of the problems which arise in the persistent application of this 
science, or which dwell in its inherent implications; but this 
should not blind us to the fact that a science like modem 
physics is itself a philosophy, at least if we believe in it and 
accept its results. We cannot simply accept physics as “science” 
and then have recourse to another science, wliich we please to 
call “philosophy,” for our preferred trath. If we accept science 
as scientific tmth, we are committed to a philosophy which 
will comprehend and be relevant to the findings of science. 
The Newtonian science, of course, has been expanded and 
modified, recently in very radical ways; but it still at any and 



THE RISE OF MODERN SOENCE 


233 

Until the twentieth century, modern society was upborne 
by this tide of faith, out of which was generated great strength, 
high achievement, and a very real sum of human good. In the 
strength of this faith it transformed itself, not everywhere but 
in strategic areas, into the great democratic, intellectualized, 
and industrialized economy we know today. No faith less 
wide or less ardent can support this tremendous organized 
economy of life and work. It is not merely the further progress 
of man, it is the continued existence of modem society that 
depends upon this faith. The hope and faith of a society is the 
measure which finally shapes and governs all of its history. 

During the nineteenth century, eloquent voices called into 
question this modem faith. Thoughtful minds became con- 
fused and uncertain as the modem age revealed its material 
potentialities, and there was a loss of nerve. In the twentieth 
century, intellecmal leaders especially in European society 
began to separate themselves from “the masses” which still 
adhered to the now familiar faith in a progressive justice and 
trath. Confused and misled by these leaders, and perverted by 
more sinister forces, European society became tom by inter- 
national and social conflicts, which already in our own time 
have well-nigh completed its ruin. The somewhat perfervid 
idealism of the earlier centuries gave way to skepticism, pes- 
simism, and moral atavism. To many, it seemed that the science 
which had promised complete insight had failed to reach ob- 
jective tmth, or had provided only a trivial trath which tells 
us nothing of what we most need to know. Society appears 
less like a moral community, it was felt, than a battleground of 
ceaseless warfare between pressure-groups; and the vaunted 
movement of progress, it was concluded, is but a foolish and 
unintelligible dogma, incompatible with a science which finds 
in nature only a determinate but nonmoral sequence of events. 

So time has brought us through another of its apparent 
circles, setting us again where Plato stood when he defended 
the intellectual and moral faith of Greece against a sophistry 



1 3 THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY 

OF MODERN SCIENCE 


In this and three sucxieeding chapters we will 
discuss the two chief trends of thought, respectively 
rationalistic and empirical, which were stimulated by the de- 
velopment of modem science, and which proposed to establish 
more firmly, and to elucidate and explain, the method and 
presuppositions of the new science. 

In pursuing this effort, philosophy becomes increasingly sep- 
arated from science, at least in name. Earlier, science had been 
but ‘‘natural philosophy.” Even in the nineteenth century 
scientific treatises were still published under this title. We 
pointed out that Parmenides had distinguished philosophy 
from science when he concentrated his attention upon the 
theoretical or logical form of Greek science, in abstraction 
from its specialized content. But this distinction, although per- 
petuated in the study of logic (which engages the form of 
scientific language in abstraction from its content) had not 
been supposed to involve a separation of philosophy from 
science. 

Today a good deal of confusion attends this subject of the 
relationship between philosophy and science. Their true rela- 


235 



THE RATIONAUSTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 237 

best illustrated by chemistry. There are still a few thinkers 
who attempt this impossible inclusion of all fact within a 
special science. The best-known form of this fallacy is the 
brand of materialism which would force physics or chemistry 
to swallow all other science. It should be clear that if the 
sciences did really compose only one science, scientists would 
have established this unitary science themselves, by empirical 
methods. The multiplication of special sciences is conclusive 
evidence that fact does not reduce to any one special hypoth- 
esis; and to insist that it must do so is merely a form of 
rationalism or dogmatian, an insistence that nature must be 
what we personally desire it to be. 

However, over and above this fact of the plurality of special 
sciences, there is another and more compelling fact which pre- 
cludes our elevation of any special science, or even the sum 
of the special sciences, into a universal comprehension of fact. 
This is the presence within each science of an apparent con- 
tradiction. Modem science rests firmly upon two criteria of 
trath. One, the primary and dominant criterion, is the shape 
and character of observable particular fact. The other criterion, 
subordinate but still indispensable, is logical consistency. Mod- 
em science assumes that some theoretical formulation will 
comprehend all the evidence of particular fact in a given 
field; and it is this assumption which supports rationalism, 
which stresses the conformity of nature everywhere to logical 
principles. Modem science escapes dogmatism, in spite of its 
apparent rationalism, by its readiess to abandon any and every 
theoretical formulation, even the most comprehensive, which 
fails to satisfy all of the empirical evidence. This compromise 
works excellently, and is the generating dynamo of scientific 
achievement; but it does not explain itself, it constimtes an ap- 
parent contradiction. The rationalistic or logical requirement, 
effectively applied in every pursuit of large theory, postulates 
some universal character in nature to which all particular fact 
must conform; but the empirical requirement postulates the 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 239 

somewhat to include in its chronological place the work of 
Francis Bacon. 

As we began our account of the rise of modem science with 
some mention of Gspemicus, we may well begin this summa^ 
of modem philosophy with Bmno, whose speculation was in 
many ways an effort to appreciate in its ftdl significance the 
revolutionary Copemican theory. The life of Giordano Bnmo 
(1548-1600) is the vignette of a stormy and religiously con- 
vulsed age. Bom in Naples, he was early initiated into the 
Dominican order. From this rigorous discipline he fled to the 
Protestant church, where he found even less comfort. He then 
wandered persecuted over Europe, teaching, quarreling, pub- 
lishing when he could. Finally he was betrayed to the Inquisi- 
tion, which burned him at the stake for his heresies. 

Brano’s blessing and curse was an intellectual imagination 
w illing to draw from the Copemican hypothesis its maximum 
consequence. If the earth is not the center of the universe, he 
argued, there is no center, nor any conceivable bound. The 
universe is infinite and homogeneous, and any part of it is as 
important and representative as any other part. God is equally 
manifest in everything — there is no privileged and locable 
“heaven.” The iiifinite universe displays the infinite being of 
God. Infinity cannot be extensively grasped. We can know 
nature only intensively, in its individual items. The item we 
know best is our individual self, of which we have an immedi- 
ate and concrete intuition. Reflection discovers in the self a 
creative activity or moral will which is the microcosm or small 
edition of the universal macrocosm, the infinite activity of 
God. Our understanding of reality must be exploratory rather 
than definitive. Nature is like a face, which we comprehend 
by appreciating its several parts in their relationship. Our per- 
sonal lives similarly set forth our souls or characters, because 
they are the creations of our wUls. The infinite character of 
God is therefore revealed to us, in some degree, in all the visible 
creation of nature, which it is our duty and privilege to study 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 


241 

brilliaat special pleader, together with his high position, gave 
him an intellectual authority which was out of proportion to 
his limited knowledge of science; but his fame and abilities 
made him the most successful advocate of modem science. 
Even Bacon’s limitations probably served him well — ^they were 
those of the European public he wished to influence. A Hume 
or a Kant would have had less immediate success. 

Bacon’s work had two sides, respectively critical and con- 
stractive. He opened his Novum Orgamim with a blast against 
all medieval learning and scholastic philosophy. Earlier scholar- 
ship, he wrote, had been little else than book learning and in- 
tellectual idolatry. It had been subservient to racial habits of 
mind (the “idols of the tribe”), personal prepossessions (the 
“idols of the cave”), tradition, especially scholastic tradition 
(the “idols of the theatre”), and habits incorporate in language 
(the “idok of the marketplace”). Nowhere had it served truth, 
which is discovered only by persistent and dutiful observation. 
Let book learning be the useless tedium of priests! Nature will 
be the study of men who directly draw from their observation 
of fact the power to control nature and man. 

Later centuries have responded perhaps too readily to this 
Baconian exhortation to cut oneself off from past intellectual 
tradition, in order to extract from sheer fact a knowledge 
which has no presuppositions whatsoever. Admirable in its 
encouragement of critical and observant habit. Bacon’s teach- 
ing suffers from its neglect of the continuity of man’s intel- 
lectual evolution. Xhis weakness becomes apparent in Bacon’s 
description of science. In truth, modem science revived and 
widened an intellectual tradition which had been preserved for 
twenty-two centuries, ever since its inception in ancient Ionia; 
but because he was ignorant or unappreciative of this long evo- 
lution, which he knew only in its medieval decline. Bacon 
failed to grasp the ideal of theoretical unity, which is a source 
and guide of modem science no less than it was of earlier 
science. 



THE RATIONALIsnC PHILOSOPHY OP MODERN SCIENCE 243 

using them and noting their implications and presuppositions; 
but only the creative scientist is qualified to reveal the 
“method” of science. Since this method is that of genius, it 
eludes definition, and can be appreciated only in its achieve- 
ments. Newton is said to have reached his gravitational hy- 
pothesis by observing the fall of an apple from a tree; but what 
was the breadth and content of thought that could read into the 
fall of an apple the fall of moon to earth and of tide to moon, 
and pursue this analogy through mathematical labyrinths never 
traced before? Was that an “induction” from observed in- 
stances? In some sort, perhaps; but in what sort? 

Bacon’s writings, if we may accept the evidence of seven- 
teenth-century literature, were the chief stimulus of the rather 
facile optimism which called itself “the Enlightenment.” The 
spokesmen of the Enlightenment regarded all earlier time, with 
some reservations respecting pagan antiquity, as an age of 
darkness from which reason or science now at last delivered 
man — and delivered him completely, into perfect light. This 
curious obliviousness of medieval antecedents was due in part 
to the linguistic shift from Latin to the European vernaculars; 
yet Francis Bacon and Descartes, the two chief literary sources 
of the Enlightenment, were Latin scholars deeply indebted to 
medieval literature. They gave expression, we must condude, 
to a real and widespread desire, current in their time, to shake 
off all the past and to advance in the power of certain new 
conceptions of nature and man to an unparalleled future. The 
writers of the Enlightenment were able to convince their con- 
temporaries, and even the later centuries as well, that reason 
appeared on earth suddenly and without antecedents, this in- 
teresting event occurring in or about the year i6oo. Thus we 
are told to see in Francis Bacon, who owed whatever he knew 
to medieval predecessors, “the father of modem science”; and 
Descartes is held up as “the founder of modem philosophy.” 
Seldom has a culture drawn such a veil between itself and its 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 245 

the cover to a new and revolutionary theory of nature, man, 
and society. What Descartes meant was nothing less than this: 
Applied mathematics is our sole science, its results are certain 
and its range unlimited, and all our other beliefs must be estab- 
lished upon or accommodated to this basic and certain 
knowledge. 

Descartes, a frail lad, was educated by Jesuits in northern 
France. He was there impressed, he tells us, only by his mathe- 
matical studies, all other instruction seeming futile. Where 
Descartes learned his contempt for scholastic philosophy and 
his inclination to Augustinian and Calvinistic theology is an 
interesting question. After sampling the salon life of Paris and 
finding it trivial and hectic, he took refuge in the army. One 
cold night before a coal fire there came to him the vision of a 
new science and a new world. Descartes is so modest in his 
account of this vision that its radical implications are easily 
overlooked. One sees the cool and lucid rationalist, and misses 
the social reformer whose utopian optimism has stimulated the 
most violent social revolutions of the modem age. This new 
science, Descartes believed, would within the near future place 
in man’s hands a power allowing him complete control over 
every human condition. Disease, poverty, crime, and war 
would be eliminated; and human society would be established 
upon a new and completely rational basis. Until such time as 
this millennium was reached, Descartes discreetly promised, he 
would conform to the usual moral conventions and live as 
other men. 

Appreciate first the scientific vision of Descartes! Greek 
geometry had analysed static surfaces and volumes, carved out 
of empty space. The new analytic geometry seemed to lay 
hold of the properties of motion itself. Given three straight 
lines at right angles and intersecting at a point, any motion 
can be described by reference to these three coordinates. A 
series of such references defines a fine, or the path of a motion; 
and a set of such lines may be used to define any physical sitta- 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 247 

science, which always supplements this doctrine of absolute 
mobile continuity with theories presupposing a discontinuity 
of stuff in nature. Nor is the conception of a mobile continuum 
itself clear or complete. Physical theory distinguishes many 
types or species of motion or energy, in its accommodation of 
thK concept of dynamic continuity to the discrete and articu- 
late world which is presented to our senses. Descartes’ concep- 
tion of nature, no less than that of Plato, harbors a dualism 
according to which a static, universal form, eternally defined 
by the axioms of geometry, invests the particular motions 
which variously manifest this eternal form; and as with Plato, 
the relation between universal form and particular motion 
must be left wholly unintelligible. Since this dynamic concept 
of nature is difficult and perhaps impossible to clarify, it is 
usually replaced by a mechanical conception which conceives 
nature to be constituted wholly of some sort of clockwork, 
intricate and infinite. Descartes himself often slipped into this 
mechanical conception when presenting or applying his dy- 
namic theory. 

One great virtue of this Cartesian concept of nature is its 
rigorous determinism. Everything that happens, at any time 
and place, even in its most minute features, is held to be com- 
pletely necessitated by its spatio-temporal context. There is no 
accident, no chance, no element of formless “matter” in nature 
itself. Events are accidental or due to chance only in the sense 
that we are ignorant of their causes and powerless to control 
these. Perfect knowledge would see everything in nature to 
be wholly necessitated, and therefore completely intelligible. 
This mechanistic concept of nature would seem to be the con- 
dition of a complete understanding and an absolute control of 
natural occurrence. 

But where does man belong in this mechanistic world? He 
cannot, Descartes concludes, belong in it at all. The mind of 
man, which observes, knows, and within its powers controls 
material nature, must be wholly other than nature, no part 



raE RATIOKALISnC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 249 

Descartes called physical nature “matter,” and said that the 
essence of matter is extension,” meaning that the true form of 
physical nature is its geometrical pattern. He similarly speaks 
of conscious experience as “mind,” and says that the “essence 
of mind” is thought or scientific analysis. This language is 
really a concession to scholastic philosophy, and a source of 
confusion in Descartes’ philosophy; but it was nevertheless 
indispensable to his system. Our immediate apprehension of 
nature is wholly unlike that colorless, soundless, perfectly 
geometrical and mobile continuum which nature becomes in 
Descartes’ science. The really physical characters of things, 
Descartes believed, are proper to external reality itself; but 
all color, taste, and other sensible character is wholly in and 
of the mind, being a mental confusion, due to our intellectual 
passivity, of the true mathematical pattern of nature. What 
earlier philosophy held to be accidental and unintelligible in 
the world, and ascribed to “matter” in distinction from 
“form,” Descartes finds to be an illusion in the mind, where, 
however, it really exists as sensations, feelings, and other non- 
rational activities. When reason is active, all of this confused 
mental material is eliminated or transmuted, to leave us with a 
rational understanding of the real motions of nature in their 
purely geometrical character. There is the real physical world, 
composed of sheer motion; there is the real mind, constituted 
by a true and rational apprehension of physical motion; and 
then there is a sort of iridescence, produced by the confusion 
of physical reality and mind, but truly nothing. The power of 
the Cartesian philosophy lay chiefly in the simplicity and 
clarity of its positive teaching. This was, that mathematical 
science truly portrays external reality. With resoluteness it 
ignored, or dismissed as illusion, whatever presented difficulties 
to this doctrine. 

Yet what a strange, stark, and really terrible doctrine it is! 
Man is to be identified with his reason, which finds in external 
reality only an infinite, colorless, silent waste of physical mo- 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 25 1 

nature, and by virtue of its intuitive power perfectly illuminate 
that limited area. He thinks of scientific theory as being already 
completed in mathematical theory, the expansion of science 
being only the continued application of this theory to ever 
new areas of nature. He does not conceive of a development 
of scientific hypothesis, stimulated by widening experience 
and reaching new basic principles. 

Modem rationalism, thus initiated by Descartes, differs im- 
portantly from the earlier rationalism established by the Greek 
philosophers. That earlier rationalism was a dualism of matter 
and form. It conceived nature to be everywhere dual, each 
existent thing and process being compounded of two sorts of 
being, namely of eternal and perfect form, and of shifting 
matter which is the source of imperfection and change. The 
Qurtesian dualism of matter and mind is something very dif- 
ferent. It conceives nature to be everywhere perfectly formed, 
what seems imperfect or unintelligible being truly an illusion 
in our minds, which are no part of nature. Yet the distinction 
between the particular changing detail and the universal geo- 
metrical form of nature must st5l be preserved, although there 
is now no philosophical place for it; and this seems to introduce 
again, but now unconsciously and disingenuously, the matter- 
form dualism which is explicitly rejected. Further, the Greek 
rationalism was genuinely idealitic. It conceived the universal 
form of nature to be the goal or end toward which all things 
strain, and in the reaching of which lies their natural good. 
Only for minds, according to modem rationalism, does form 
constitute an ideal of this sort. Nature is perfect in its absolute 
geometry; but imperfect man must still strain to know this 
form, the intuition of which is its cognitive ideal. Does this 
mean that nature is wholly good, that every prospect pleases 
and only man is vile.? Or does it mean that nature is nonmoral, 
its values arising solely out of its utility for man ? Or is nature 
beyond good and evil, is it a sort of absolute contentment be- 
yond all striving? It is evident that the Cartesian dualism, in 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE I53 

in the method and form of modem science. Because it seemed 
to make the new science simple and rational; because it seemed 
to offer a much needed ground for intellectual and political 
authority; because it promised a social millennium in an “age 
of reason”; because it expressed the high optimism of the 
Renaissance and seemed to turn its back upon the past; because, 
paradoxically, it also brought into philosophy certain moral 
and religious conceptions implicit in the Puritan Reformation; 
because it verbally bridged the gap between scholastic theology 
and the new scientific outlook; and, finally, because it was 
presented in a prose so lucid and effective that it has remained 
the model of French style ever since — for these reasons, the 
Cartesian philosophy had enormous mfluence. It established a 
rationalistic tradition which developed and modified itself with 
each succeeding generation, to become a permanent factor in 
modem thought; and its importance and success were not, of 
course, without reason, being due to the undeniable rational 
element in modem science, which cleaves to its theoretical 
form and everywhere requires the accommodation of fact to 
the requirements of logic. We shall not be able to estimate the 
value of the thought of Descartes, consequently, until we have 
come to some conclusion concerning this relation of empirical 
fact to logical form. What Descartes too much neglected, we 
saw, was the empirical element in modern science, this being 
its most characteristic and important element. 

Notes for Further Reading 

1. Boulting, W., Giordano Bruno. London, K. Paul, Trench, 

Triibner and Company, Ltd., 1916. 

2. McClure, M. T., Bacon: Selectio 7 is. New York, Charles Scrib- 

ner’s Sons, 1928. 

3. Wheelwright, P., Bacon, Hobbes, Locke: Selectiojis. Garden 

City, Doubleday Doran and Company, 1930. 

4. Kennedy, G., Bacon, Hobbes, Locke: Selections. New York, 

Doubleday Doran and Company, 1937. 



14 


THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY 
OF MODERN SCIENCE 

(Continued) 


F 

JLj SPECIALLY ON THE CONTINENT OF EUROPE, THE 

thought of Descartes became the starting-point of 
many who wished to emancipate themselves from past tradi- 
tion, and to establish life and society upon a purely rational, 
indisputable basis. As we have seen, the Cartesian system was 
by no means so complete a break with earlier thought as he 
and his contemporaries believed. His mathematical concept of 
physical nature improved upon that of Pythagoras; his dualism 
of physical and mental being gave philosophical room to the 
Christian dualism of world and spirit, the sacred and the pro- 
fane; his theology was Augustinian and scholastic. But these 
traditional elements, which allowed Descartes to reach his 
readers, largely served as a bridge which could be crossed and 
then burned and forgotten. They constituted a sort of religious 
background, taking care of the inscrutable and allowing the 
foreground of thought to be brilliantly illuminated. By most of 
Descartes’ readers, a method so powerful and a reason so lucid 
was expected to overcome every problem. Men of less genius 
did not see that his power was the clarity with which he 
perceived the limitations of his rationalistic method. Descartes 



THE RATIONAUSTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 257 

any better than we understand how physical body affects 
mind? To say that the motion lost by one body is only trans- 
ferred to the body with which it collides allows us to describe 
such events in mathematical equations; but it does not explain 
how the transfer of motion takes place. Motion is a bodily 
property, and how can bodies exchange properties? The causal 
coimection remains unexplained and inexplicable, and we must 
say that one physical event only occasions another, the true 
cause being God. The Cartesian doctrine, at first sight so lucid 
and rational, evaporates into religious mysticism. The French 
cleric Malebranche welcomed this conclusion. The ph3^ical 
world, he suggested, is but a myth, all our experience proceed- 
ing in God, who is the sole agent and ceaseless creator of all 
that is. This idealistic mysticism was later developed by 
Berkeley. 

But two continental thinkers, Spinoza and Leibniz, made 
valiant attempts to modify the Cartesian system in such a way 
as to meet this matter-mind problem without sacrifice of the 
Cartesian faith in science. Benedict Spinoza (1632-1677) at- 
tempted a solution by means of the concept of an absolute 
correspondence or parallelism between physical and mental 
processes. To every mental condition, he supposed, there cor- 
responds a physical condition; and vice versa. Our will to move 
and our bodily motion are not cause and effect, but two aspects 
of one and the same concrete event. Similarly, every sensation 
is the mental aspect of some bodily condition. The real world, 
in short, is everywhere at once mental and physical, just as a 
box must have an inside and an outside, or a curved line a 
convex side and a concave side. Matter and mind are not two 
substances; they are two most basic properties of one and the 
same substance. 

This conception of psychophysical parallelism has proved 
useful, even indispensable, in human psychology; and we can- 
not doubt that it expresses a biological fact. Also, it suggests 
a more general conception which is intellectually emancipating. 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 259 

man would regenerate society and establish it on a firm basis; 
but he nowhere rationally established even this assumption. So 
Spinoza wrote his Ethics, a treatise of rational morality and 
rational religion. 

We possess today a considerable body of theoretical science, 
the authority of which is seldom seriously questioned; but after 
three centuries of theoretical research, we have still no au- 
thoritative science of ethics. Kant, who was the profoundest 
student of this problem, concluded there can be none, because 
freedom and authority are reciprocally exclusive. But Spinoza 
did not doubt the possibility of a rational ethical theory. His 
faith was due in part to his need, which would not be denied. 
He was the son of a Jewish family, driven from Spain to Hol- 
land by the persecutions of the Inquisition. In Holland, his in- 
tellectual audacity brought him into collision with orthodox 
Jewry, which excommunicated him from the synagogue. 
Spinoza needed a rational religion, one that would leave him 
intellectually free, yet unite him with his fellows despite all 
differences of confession and race. He became the first modern 
exponent of a liberal religion which would carry into creative 
faith the intellectual powers active and creative in science. He 
had a second ground of faith. Although Spinoza subscribed to 
the Cartesian science, he was not only nor even pr imar ily a 
Cartesian. In his youth he had steeped himself in Jewish and 
other scholastic theology, and he never renounced certain large 
tenets of scholastic doctrine. The Puritan conception which 
allows to nature no intrinsic value, but sees in it only a physical 
mechanism created to serve man’s moral purpose, never found 
lodgment in the mind of Spinoza. Nature was for him what it 
was for the Stoics, the material expression of universal and 
divine Being. Both metaphysically and morally, Spinoza is a 
modem Stoic, one who adapts the Stoic concept of nature to 
the supposed requirements of modem science. The main out- 
line of his metaphysics is as follows: There is but one Sub- 
stance, mfinite in extent and variety, but absolute in its unity. 



THE RATIONALISTIC PaiLOSOPHY OF MODERN SOENCE z6l 

pendent substance, in some degree effecting its own mental 
processes, and therewith its physical processes. And in fact, 
Spinoza assumes much more than this bare choice. To choose 
the rational life, he says, is to resist the passions, temptations, 
and feelings induced in us by our immediate environment, 
which compel us to pursue pleasure, fame, position, wealth, 
and other “worldly” goods. To live rationally is to live wholly 
in and for an “intellectual love of God,” i.e. a rational under- 
standing of ourselves as mere items in the universal Substance. 
Spinoza implies that the individual is free to determine his 
life, and that he will find his true good in an intelligent and 
voluntary participation in a universal divine Process. 

We may accept the ethical purpose of Spinoza, which was 
to establish a rational and intelligent moral science, without 
being disturbed by the metaphysical inconsistencies of his 
ethical theory. In the same way we may accept his call to an 
independent and intelligent religious faith without identifying 
ourselves with his specific conclusions, which were determined 
by his faulty interpretation of science. Spinoza was adamandy 
opposed to all revealed religion, with its appeal to past au- 
thority, its dogmatic per^cution of heresies, and its anthropo- 
morphism. The only true God, he taught, is that eternal, im- 
mutable, univereal Substance, which, wholly unlike our human 
selves, is omnipotent and infinite, yet accessible to our rational 
intuition. Spinoza’s criticism of biblical sources initiated a new 
era of critical and scientific religious study, and was the im- 
portant forerunner of the critic^ historical science of today. 
He widened the religious oudook of his age; and his work 
should have initiated a creative movement, reaching new re- 
ligious truth by applying to religion the faculties developed by 
a free and observant science. His achievement remains great, 
therefore, after we discount his ethical and religious teaching 
as too rationalistic and intellectual, too solitary and aloof, too 
unrelated to emotional and social actualities. 

The chief philosophical influence of Spinoza, over and above 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MCHJEBN SCIENCE 263 

The fact was that philosophers had now to reconcile, and 
if possible to synthesize, two important but quite different in- 
tellectual traditions, developing quite distinct concepts of na- 
ture and knowledge. One was the Greek and medieval tradi- 
tion, which drew, so to speak, a horizontal line through nature, 
dividing every natural thing into a more lowly matter striving 
upwards toward its true form, and a transcendental form con- 
descending to this lowly matter. The other tradition was this 
newer Cartesian conception,, which drew a vertical line divid- 
ing physical reality off from another reality called “mind.” 
Since this physical reality was also usually called “matter,” it 
was mistakenly given many of the properties of the Greek 
matter; and this led to all sorts of confusion and ambiguity. 
No one tried more brilliantly, or more desperately, to make 
sense of this confusion of Greek and Cartesian metaphysics 
than the German philosopher Leibniz. 

Gottfried Willxlm Leibniz (1646-1716) was, like Descartes, 
a mathematical genius; and, again like Descartes, he wished to 
conceive of nature in such a way as to make it wholly con- 
formable to mathematical thory. Descartes, the inventor of 
analytical geometry, had conceived nature to be wholly fluid 
and continuous, to be just geometrical motion. Leibniz was the 
inventor of the infinitesimal calculus, a rather paradoxical 
theory which requires us to conceive of any finite quantity as 
being composed of an infinite number of infinitesimally small 
quantities. The application of this theory requires a concep- 
tion of nature just the opposite of that of Descartes. Descartes 
had to suppose that every apparently solid and discrete body is 
really mobile, fluid, and continuous with its context, its ap- 
parent solidity and ILxity being due to the constant pattern of 
its motion. Leibniz, on the contrary, had to conceive every 
apparent continuity in nature, e.g. a line, or path of motion, 
to be made up of those discrete infinitesimals which compose, 
when there are infinitely enough of them, finite and visible 
things. 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 265 

It was Descartes who first taught, in modem times, that our 
ordinary experience is only a confused version of our clear 
radonal intuition of true being. Spinoza, thereupon, supposed 
that animals and other subhuman beings are possessed of an even 
lower and more confused mentality. Leibniz similarly supposes 
that the extended physical world arises from our confused 
vision of myriads of nonextended monads which to a perfect 
vision would be separately and individually known. But the 
uniformity or natural law which characterizes this extended 
and illusory physical world is not altogether an illusion. It 
represents the true character of the constituent monads, which 
were created by God in such manner as to exhibit, when con- 
fusedly seen, these real uniformities instituted by God. 

The monads, Leibtdz taught, are purely spiritual, in- 
destructible, self-determinate beings. Each monad, from the 
beginning to the end of time, exhibits only its own successive 
states, in the order determined by God at its creation. You 
and I are such monads, temporarily attached to myriad other 
monads constituting our bodies. Our experience did not begin 
with our birth, it began with the creation; and it will continue, 
after death has dissolved our bodies, to the end of time. Since 
each monad is wholly self-determined, there is no real interac- 
tion anywhere. When you see me, I am really here; but your 
perception of me is not due to my presence, it was instituted 
in you, and ordained to appear at this time, by God at the 
creadon; and it was then also ordained that I should really be 
here at the time you see me, so that your perception, although 
wholly subjective, is nevertheless objectively true. Leibniz is 
an Occasionalist in this demal of real causation in nature; but 
it is to the original creation, and not to the present intermedia- 
tion of God, that he looks for the explanation of all apparent 
causation. 

This doctrine gets impossibly involved. First, we must sup- 
pose that a monad really sees other monads, but sees them only 
confusedly as extended objects, much as separate points are 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MITOERN SOENCE 


267 

an organic whole “ideally” controlled by the Supreme Monad 
which is God, Presumably this Monad, which ideally controls 
all other monads, is another Person than that which actually 
created all monads whatsoever, including Himself. 

The curious, intricate, elusive, and ultimately unthinkable 
system of Leibniz was the work of a man whose mathematical 
genius took him into a game with manipulable symbols. These 
can be thrown at will into all sorts of symbolic patterns; and 
the problem is then to give to the symbols descriptive meanings. 
The relationship of these patterns to observable fact may be 
remote or nonexistent; yet they can be defined with mathemati- 
cal precision, Leibniz is the rednctio ad abmrdum of the ra- 
tionalistic dogma, revived by Descartes, that the clarity and 
distinctness of ideas, i.e. their logical manipulability, is their 
truth. Yet Leibniz applied this faculty of free mathematical 
invention to very red problems, for example to the problem 
of freedom in a physically necessitated world, and to the prob- 
lem — if it be another and not the same problem — of the rela- 
tion of particular fact to general hypothesis. His conclusion 
was that freedom and individuality or particularity are real 
and ultimate, but that natural law and generality are also real 
in a certain sense, because God so created free individuals that 
they would seem to behave according to general principles. 
This conclusion probably amounts to the admission that free- 
dom and individuality are not to be intelligibly reconciled with 
the concept of naturd necessity, but must be affirmed by an act 
of religious faith. 

Leibniz was the greatest logician since Aristotle and prior 
to Bertrand Russell; and he was the originator of the move- 
ment which led to modem logic. His fertile logicd imagina- 
tion generated severd ideas which have had profitable applica- 
tions in science. One of these, already mentioned, was lus idea 
of organic relationship. Another was his notion that space and 
time, at least in their mathematical formulations, are relationd 
orders of things and not the absolute media which Newton 



THE RATIONALISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 269 

sized mathematical principles, their different mathematical sys- 
tems pointing to very opposite concepts of “reality.” Spinoza, 
less bound by physical science, cultivated a “rational intuition” 
which apparently, if we may judge by its very different results 
in different thinkers, allows one to intuit any sort of “absolute 
reality” one happens to prefer. It is clear, perhaps, that this 
rationalistic philosophy is cognitively irresponsible. We know 
today that mathematical theories can be made to order, in such 
a way as to define any sort of material we may imagine; and 
this means that mathematical theory, in and by itself, is no 
indication of the sort of world we actually inhabit. But a free 
“rational intuition” of Spinoza’s sort is even more irresponsible. 
It does not even conform to strict logic, as does mathematical 
theory. 

Notice, once more, how this modem rationalism differs from 
the Greek and medieval rationalism! Plato also supposed that 
true knowledge arises from self-evident principles given to the 
reason, and that these rational principles define the eternal and 
universal structure which is discovered by science in the world. 
But the Greek rationalism did not identify this “reality” with 
existent nature, as does modem rationalism. It identified “real- 
ity” with the form of nature; but it also postulated a material 
element which is the source of accident, defect, and particular- 
ity in nature. Modem rationalism renounces this dualism of 
form and matter — it takes existent reality to be pure form, and 
holds that what is not pure form arises as a subjective illusion, 
due to confusion in the mind. 

It is evident that this rationalistic doctrine assumes, but with- 
out admitting it, the cooperation of the senses in natural knowl- 
edge. Knowledge of universal principles would tell us nothing 
about tMs world, which is a consensus of particular fact. Only 
the senses can reveal the particular configuration of nature at 
any place and time. Geometry could not tell us that there exists 
a sun with just so many planets, or that Jupiter has four moons, 
or that you were bom and now exist. Leibniz was aware of this 



THE RAUONALISnC PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 27 1 

3. Luce, A. A., Berkeley and Malebranche. London and New 

York, Oxford University Press, 1934. 

4. Wild, J., Spinoza: Selections. New York, Charles Scribner’s 

Sons, 1930. 

5. Spinoza, B., Ethics. New York, E. P. Dutton and Company, 

Everyman’s edition, 1911. Also other translations. 

6. Broad, C. D,, five Types of Ethical Theory. London and New 

York, Cambridge University Press, 1934. 

7. McKeon, R. The Philosophy of Spinoza. Boston, Longmans, 

Green and Company, 1928. 

8. Wolfson, H. A., The Philosophy of Spinoza. Cambridge, 

Harvard University Press, 1934. 

• 9. Wolfson, A., Spinoza. New York, Modem Classics, Inc., 1932. 

10. Roth, L., Spinoza. Boston, Little, Brown and Company, 1929. 
There are also studies of Spinoza by Gunn, Caird, Martineau, 

Joachim, PoUock, and Duff. 

11. Leibniz, G. W., Philosophical Works, trans. Duncan. New 

Haven, The Tuttle, Morehouse and Taylor Company, 1890. 

12. Langley, A. G., The New Essays. La Salle, 111 ., The Open 

Court Publishii^ Company, 1896. 

13. Latta, R., The Monadology, etc. London and New York, The 

Oxford University Press, 1925. 

14. Montgomery, G. R., The Correspondence of Leibniz. La Salle, 

111 ., The Open Court Publishing Company, 1902, 1918. 

15. Rhys, E., ed., Leibnis^ Philosophical Writings. New York, E. 

P. Dutton and Company, Inc., 1934. 

16. Carr, H. W., Leibniz. London and New York, Oxford Uni- 

versity Press, 1929. 

17. The Monadology of Leibniz. Los Angeles, University 

of Southern California, 1930. 

18. Merz, J. Y., Leibniz. Edinburgh, Philosophical Classics for Eng- 

lish Readers, 1886. 

19. Russell, B,, A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz. 

New York, The Macmillan Company, 1900, 1937. 

20. L6vy-Bruhl, L., A History of Modem Philosophy in France. 
La SaUe, 111 ., The Open Court Publishing Company, 1899. 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 2^3 

empirical in its establishment of universal principles such as that 
of gravitation, which had to be reached by observation and ex- 
perimental hypothesis. It is not self-evident that bodies must 
attract each other according to just this formula. Reason alone, 
it follows, does not tell us what sort of a world this is. The 
nature of nature awaits discovery. Science must continually 
construct new hypotheses, and retain these only so long as they 
meet the observable facts. 

The principles of rationalistic philosophy can be stated fairly 
simply. The principles of empiricism are more difficult to ex- 
pound, because their final implications are obscure and perhaps 
inexhaustible. How, for example, shall we explain the fact that 
theoretical science, although it willingly subjects its special 
hypotheses to factual confirmation or disproof, still assumes 
that some general theory must meet all of the facts? Empirical 
science still seems to rely upon the self-evident principles of 
logic, assuring the success of theoretical analysis. The early 
nominalists, who were the forerunners of empirical philosophy, 
too easily disposed of this difficulty. Reality is made up of indi- 
vidual and unique things, they said; and theories are merely 
verbal or mental constructions. We will find that this is by no 
means the whole truth. Scientific theories are indeed composed 
of words or ideas in our minds; but if we are to distinguish 
between a true theory and a false theory, we must suppose that 
the true theory indicates, and the false theory fails to indicate, 
a real pattern in the real world, and not merely a pattern in 
our minds. 

Francis Bacon, who instructed his readers to look only to 
nature for their knowledge, inclined to this nominalistic view; 
but he cannot be said to have presented an intelligible theory 
of knowledge. Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), whose politick 
philosophy we have already noticed, served Bacon as a sort of 
secretary in the old minister’s declining years. Hobbes explicitly 
subscribed to nominalism in his analysis of cognition; but his 
materialistic philosophy implies a rationalistic theory of knowl- 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 275 

him to avoid the difficulties of the Cartesian dualism and to 
understand mental processes as manifestations of causal inter- 
action proceeding between the human organism and its natural 
environment. Mental process, Hobbes supposed, is only phya- 
cal process of a special and complicated sort. Psychology ought 
therefore to pattern itself upon physics. Just as physical science 
divides into geometry and mechanics — ^the first defining the 
static structure of matter and the second describing the inter- 
active processes of matter — so psychology will divide itself 
into two studies, one discovering the permanent principles of 
human behavior and the other describing the temporal proc- 
esses of human life. This may sound very empirical and scien- 
tific, but its analogy between physical dynamics and a psychol- 
ogy of human purpose betrays an irremediable confusion of 
mind. This confusion becomes apparent when Hobbes identifies 
the two divisions of psychology respectively with ethics and 
politics. Hobbes here confused an empirical psychology, which 
would seek a general statement of how men do in fact behave, 
with a normative moral code prescribing how men should 
behave. Hobbes was betrayed by his unconscious rationalism. 
Because he believed that there are absolute mechanical prin- 
ciples to which everything must of necessity conform, he could 
conclude that there are absolute rational principles to which all 
human beings must of necessity conform; and so he inevitably 
came to confuse moral principles, which tell us how man ought 
to behave, with scientific axioms telling us how men must 
behave. Ever since Hobbes, materialism with its confusion of 
moral and descriptive principles has hindered the scientific 
study of man and society, and endangered freedom. 

Hobbes did not know, we conclude, what constitutes em- 
pirical science, in spite of the fact that his fresh and often dis- 
cerning study of man helped to inaugurate an empirical psy- 
chology and sociology. Yet when he turned to a toect study 
of human knowledge, he committed himself very definitely 
to the principle, out of which issues fina lly a true empiric^ 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 277 

prepossession, are pseudoconcepts, or meaningless words of 
this sort. 

Hobbes’ materialism and the political absolutism which de- 
rived from his materialistic principles seem to have exerted 
considerable influence on the continent of Europe. In Britain 
his materialistic rationalism and his political absolutism found 
little response. This was not the case with his psychology and 
his nominalistic theory of knowledge, which had important 
consequences. These studies revived the critical attitude of the 
medieval nominalists who had opposed the scholastic rational- 
ism; and they initiated modem critical philosophy, which un- 
dertakes a critical analysis, and reaches a very cautious estimate, 
of the validity and scope of theoretical knowledge. Chiefly 
through Hobbes there came to be developed that subjectivistic 
and introspective sort of psychology which studies mental con- 
tents in isolation from their physiological and external condi- 
tions, Recent psychology has largely freed itself from this sub- 
jectivistic and sterile tradition. In philosophy, however, 
Hobbes’ subjectivistic analysis of mind has continued to char- 
acterize an introspective “epistemology,” which narrows and 
defeats philosophical speculation. But Hobbes, in spite of his 
faulty psychology and his absolutistic premises, was never- 
theless an important channel through which the critical philos- 
ophy of the later Middle Ages came down the centuries to our- 
selves. 

This critical philosophy was primarily directed against ra- 
tionalist tradition. Its positive purpose, however, was the 
defense of an empirical science basing its conclusions wholly 
upon observable fact. Johm Locke (1632—1704) is generally 
and with reason regarded as the chief founder of modem em- 
pirical philosophy. We have already noticed Locke’s political 
theory, which still provides the theoretical basis of modem 
democratic government. We should see in Locke’s general 
philosophy, published in 1691 in the famous Essay Concermng 



the EMPiraCAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 279 

conformity to some known and supposedly indubitable prin- 
ciple the test of the truth of a new hypothesis. Locke is excus- 
ably vague, and sometimes mistaken, concerning just how new 
truth is obtained. 

His Essay opens with a critique of dogmatism and rational- 
ism. In his political writings he had attacked the concept of 
divine monarchical right, because this was the most powerful 
and widespread of the dogmas which prevented individual 
assumption of the responsibility of self-government. He now 
attacks all dogma, and indicts the dogmatic habit of mind itself. 
There are, he says, no “innate ideas.” He means that there are 
no principles wHch are innate to the mind, prior to experience, 
or which need no confirmation by experience. All ideas and all 
knowledge derive from experience, our surest ideas being those 
which experience most widely confirms. What rationalistic 
science takes to be infallible and self-evident principles, he 
says, are in fact only nommal definitions^ prescribing certain 
fifties of meaning and conventional use. They do not amount 
to real definitions, defining once and for all the ultimate natures 
of things. Such real definition, Locke implies, is beyond our 
powers. Our knowledge of things is partial, tentative, progres- 
sive, never final nor definitive. Locke was a lifelong student of 
science; he practiced medicine, cultivated the friendship of 
leading scientists, and kept abreast of scientific invention. He 
did not confine himself to an appreciation of mathematical 
physics. He conceived science to be discovery — not a set of 
theoretical principles, but the inexhaustible generator of 
theories and principles. 

Negative in its denial of self-evident truth, positive in its 
aflGrmation of the creative and exploratory power of science, 
Locke’s view is negative again in its denial of universal knowl- 
edge, i.e. knowledge of the universe in its totality. He was 
driven to his study of cognition, he writes, by his perception 
of the fruitlessness of current metaphysical discussions, in 
which philosophers threw at one ano±er different conceptions 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 28 1 

sensory evidence and theoretical hypothesis; but in fact he 
denied it, by relegating all that is not rationally formulated to a 
limbo of sense-illusion. The distinction between what is per- 
ceived and what is conceived lies within science itself. Science 
includes both clear and explicit theory and the inchoate evi- 
dence which is organized by means of theory. We owe to the 
empirical philosophers the insight that science is the concrete 
but intelligent apprehension of particular fact, ue. of nature 
itself as it observably exists. What the empiricists failed to 
make clear was the relation between these two elements, the 
formulated theory and the particular observable facts. Some- 
how the particularized evidence at once distinguishes itself 
from the general theory, and supports the general theory. But 
how? 

Locke took refuge in the oversimple distinction between 
primary and secondary qualities, in order to explain the 
scientist’s transmutation of sensed particular fact into scientific 
knowledge. Nature, he assumed, is a collection of real things or 
substances, each of which has its real and intrinsic properties. 
Some of these properties enter into experience unchanged; and 
in regard to these, our perception is truthful and scientific. 
But many of the characters of perception are not truthful. 
They are the effects in us of the actual properties of the thing; 
and these effects may little resemble their external causes. 
Locke’s suggestion is that science should discover the true 
natures of things by discerning and reflecting upon the p rimar y 
properties. (This suggestion is revived in a corrected form in 
the “critical realism” of today. But Locke’s main conception, 
which states knowledge to arise as the result of a process of 
comparison, abstraction, and recombination effected upon the 
materials of sensation, points in a very different direction, lead- 
ing to modern idealism.) Locke does not, as a matter of fact, 
provide a single consistent description of cognitive process. 
Sometimes he is a realist, and holds knowledge to be at least in 
some degree identical with the substances which it describes; 



the empirical philosophy of modern SaENCE 283 

insisring that truth is the correspondence of idea with fact, he 
seems to be saying that knowledge is a perception of agreement 
or disagreement among ideas. Only very cursorily does he now 
discuss “the agreement of ideas with real existence.” These 
later chapters might have been written by a rationalistic fol- 
lower of Descartes. Yet Locke may not have meant to say that 
the axioms of mathematics and the generative principles of 
morality are innate and self-evident truths, established by pure 
reason. In attributing absoluteness or certainty to these axioms 
and principles, he may have meant only that they are the 
widest, most certain, and best attested deliverances of experi- 
ence, confirmed by all observation. In spite of many requests 
that he should do so, it might be added, Locke was never able 
to present the set of principles basic to a “moral science” 
parallehng mathematics. He felt, perhaps, that these absolute 
moral principles were implicit in his political theory. If so, they 
would comprise an affiimation of the moral, self-responsible, 
and essentially virtuous character of individual man. 

Locke’s limitations were also his strength. He was a man of 
incomparable “common sense,” able to state philosophical con- 
victions in language intelligible and convincing to the reader 
untrained in philosophy. At the same time, he had an intellec- 
tual shrewdness and a superlative honesty which led him to 
the heart of a problem, and which usually saved him, much as 
he wished to save others, from losing his feet among words and 
ideas. His intellectual modesty, moreover, relieved him from 
the necessity of elaborating a completed philosophy, meeting 
and resolving all of the problems which he himself raised. 
Locke did not see these problems as clearly as Hume and Kant 
would later see them. He conceived of the pursuit of knowl- 
edge as a campaign which is to be tactically advanced on many 
fronts, and which neither requires nor allows a global strategy. 
He did not believe, we noted, in the possibility of a universal, 
comprehensive study of fact. Yet his very limitations allowed 
him to establish, more securely than his predecessors had done. 



rHE EMPnUCAL PHILOSOPHY OP MODERN SCIENCE iSj 

be removed, it had to be elaborated into a system making clear 
its whole implication. This was done by George Berkeley, 
writing not long after the publication of the Essay. 

George Berkeley (1683-1753), a student preparing for the 
minis try at Dublin University, was one of those who were 
entranced by this “new way of ideas.” If knowledge is wholly 
derived from mental impressions or ideas, young Berkeley pon- 
dered, how can the knowledge thus obtained discover to us 
anything peculiarly nonmental, material, and inert? In a bril- 
liant psychological study, Berkeley showed that many of the 
experienced characters which we unhesitatingly ascribe to 
material nature are really the action or eifect of sensory activi- 
ties proceeding in the organism. Everything that is directly 
perceived, he concluded, is conditioned by the nature of the 
percipient organism, i.e. by our own nature. Berkeley realized 
that this conclusion was pregnant with philosophical conse- 
quences; and very soon, while still in his twenty-second year, 
he published The Principles of Human Krumledge, destined to 
become another of the classical texts of modem philosophy. 
His thesis is that of idealism. A reality that is perceived and 
known by mind, he argues, must itself be of a mental character, 
related to that which apprehends it. If reality were completely 
nonmental, wholly unlike and unrelated to our minds, there 
could be no real connection between nature and mind, and 
knowledge would be impossible. 

The conscious human organism or mind, Berkeley con- 
cludes, enters as a factor into every sense-perception; and if 
perception is the material source of tmth, this mental character 
will consequently qualify all that "v^^e know. The world that we 
know, he continues, is constitutively determined in all of its 
character by the fact that it is perceived, i.e. by its relation to 
the perceiving mind. We may not therefore accept a science 
which ostensibly defines nature, but which does not acknowl- 
edge this mental character qualifying aU our immediate experi- 
ence of nature. If the mental character of “being-perceived” 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 287 

Berkeley establishes his conclusion that all reality is mental? 
He used his mentalism, indeed, to discredit the materialistic 
doctrine which teaches that external reality is really composed 
of unconscious material atoms, moving according to the laws 
of mechanics. This mechanistic science may explain how physi- 
cal things interact with and upon each other; but it does not 
yet explain how things act upon our minded selves, producing 
mental effects in conscious organisms. The causal coimection, 
Berkeley might have said, presupposes some deep sort of con- 
tinuity, likeness, or even identity between what is cause and 
what is effect, ue. between the external world and its effects in 
conscious perception. 

It should be recognized that this idealistic argument is still 
possessed of force. That there is causal interaction between 
the living organism and its external environment most of us 
will readily admit; but we do not always admit that the exist- 
ence of this causal process requires us to explain the external 
world in terms of its interaction with animals and men, as well 
as in terms of its inorganic interactions. The cognitive response 
of man to nature implies something with respect to nature. 
We must also explain the living organism in terms of its inter- 
actions with the external world; and this duly leads us to a 
biochemistry and even a psychophysics; but this latter implica- 
tion Berkeley did not or would not see. His purpose was to 
make a frontal attack upon materialism of the Hobbesian sort, 
which, when taken alone, he quite properly saw, invalidates all 
moral, religious, and intellectual truth, fails to explain our 
immediate perception of natural quality, and finally makes un- 
intelligible the distinction between living and nonliving things. 
Both materialism and idealism, we may conclude, are partial 
truths. The materialist wishes to recognize only such causal 
relations as connect inorganic substances, ignormg the relations 
between conscious organisms and their environment; the 
idealist, on the contrary, recognizes only this latter sort of 
relation, and neglects the causal processes discovered in inor- 



the empirical philosophy of modern science 289 

called “universal form” — ^is apprehended by the intellect or 
reason. The medieval mysticism which sought an immediate, 
even a sensory, apprehension of divine and ultimate Being 
consequently involved a new evaluation and a rehabilitation of 
particular fact, which Greek science and philosophy had be- 
litded and neglected. Both assumptions — ^that we know par- 
ticular character only through the senses and general character 
only through the intellect — ^may be mistaken. The writer be- 
lieves them to be so. But they are still widely and unhesitat- 
ingly affirmed; and they help to reveal to us certain aesthetic, 
moral, and religious motives which have advanced the develop- 
ment of empirical science and philosophy in the modem age. 

Many of Berkeley’s subsidiary arguments, applying or sup- 
porting his idealistic thesis, are acute and have been confirmed 
by later thought. For example, he rejects the distinction, at 
least as it was then made, between primary and secondary 
qualities. We cannot separate out of our experience, he points 
out, certain perceived characters which persist unchanged -by 
our perception of them, to leave aside those which are trans- 
formed by the process of perception. Every perceived char- 
acter whatsoever, he shows, is subjectively conditioned — size 
and shape just as much as color or warmth. In the sense of 
being subjectively conditioned, therefore, all perceived char- 
acters are secondary; and it is further clear that all of those 
characters which had been elevated as primary and absolutely 
truthful, such as size and shape, are known to us only by way 
of the so-called secondary characters. A world without color, 
without light and shade, and without tactile quality would 
present no sensible sizes or shapes, but would fuse into inarticu- 
late unity. Berkeley, however, would call all qualities primary, 
rather than secondary, because he holds that in spite of their 
being conditioned by the percipient organism, they are the real 
and ultimate qualities of the world. Today, the cogency of 
Berkeley’s criticism of primary qualities is fairly generally 
conceded. All perceived characters, it is usually ^owed, are 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 


291 


rialism; and if we are to allow that idealism is an intelligible 
doctrine, we must allow realistic truth to concepts and renounce 
the nominalistic position. 

We have now seen several sorts of idealism, and it is im- 
portant' to distinguish them. First, we met Greek idealism, 
which did not deny but emphatically affirmed the reality of 
matter of a certain sort. Greek idealism was dualistic, it ex- 
plained each existent thing as a compound of matter and form. 
It was idealistic in the sense that it attributed to the forms 
which invest things a high or “ideal” beauty, a supreme right- 
ness and significance — ^not that it conceived things, or even 
forms, to be peculiarly mental or immaterial in the modem 
sense. Modem idealism, unlike the Greek, is monistic; it 
denies the reality of matter, and attributes reality only to 
mind. Modem idealism has two forms. Rationalistic or Leib- 
nizian idealism defines the mind in terms of its intellectual 
processes and its conceptual knowledge; and it consequently 
conceives reality to be some totality of intellectual process. 
Perceptual or Berkeleian idealism defines the mind as a pano- 
rama of sensory experience; and it consequently conceives the 
universe to be a larger expanse of such experience. Both con- 
ceptions are difiicult, vague, and ultimately unthinkable. Their 
value is to remind us that the conscious intellectual and per- 
ceptual processes of man really exist. These processes cannot be 
argued out of court; and they make unacceptable any concep- 
tion of nature which leaves them inexplicable or unaccounted 
for. Man, and all that he is, is part of nature, and a clue to 
nature. But simply to define nature as a larger replica of psy- 
chological process seems rather futile, not to say puerile. 
Plato, whatever his inadequacies, was more mature in his per- 
ception of the problem and in his dualisdc solution of it. 

We noticed that Berkeley’s idealistic metaphysics, with its 
acknowledgment of a “notion” of mind and universal being, 
required a departure from his nominalistic theory of knowl- 
edge, An early Common-Place Book in which the young 



the empirical philosophy of modern science 293 

2, Laird, J., Hobbes. London and New York, Oxford University- 

Press, 1934. 

3, Taylor, A. E., Hobbes. New York, Dodge Publishing Com- 

pany, 1908. 

4. Robertson, G. C., Hobbes. New York, Charles Scribner’s Sons, 

1 886, 

F* J, E. Woodbridge, M. W. Calkins, G. Kennedy, P. Wheeling, 
and others have edited selections from Hobbes, 

5. Locke, J., An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. New 

York, E. P. Dutton and Company, Inc., 1901, 

6* The Essay ^ ed. A. C. Fraser. London and New York, 

Oxford University Press, 1901. 

7. Lamprecht, S. P., Locke: Selections. New York, Columbia Uni- 

versity Press, 1928. 

8. Calkins, M. W., Lockers Essay: Selections. La Salle, 111 ., The 

Open Court Publishing Company, 1905, 1920. 

9. Morris, C. R., Locke^ Berkeley, and Hume. London and New 

York, Oxford University Press, 1931. 

10. Alexander, S-, Locke. New York, Dodge Publishing Company, 

1908, 

1 1. Green, T. H., Introduction to Hume's Treatise. Several editions. 

12. Fowler, Th., Locke. New York, The Macmillan Company, 

1906, 

13. Fraser, A, C., Locke. London and New York, Oxford Uni- 

versity Press, 1890, 1901. 

14. Gibson, J., Lockers Theory of Knowledge. New York, The 

Macmillan Company, 1917. 

15. Berkeley, G., Works, ed. A. C Fraser. London and New York, 

Oxford University Press, 1871. 

16. Calkins, M. W., Berkeley: Selections. New York, Charles Scrib- 

ner’s Sons, 1929. 

17. Fraser, A. C., Berkeley. London and New York, Oxford Uni- 

versity Press, 1899. 

18. Hicks, G. D., Berkeley. London, Ernest Benn, Ltd., 1932. 

19. Johnston, G. A,, The Development of Berkeley's Philosophy. 

New York, The Macmillan Company, 1923. 

20. Wild, J., George Berkeley. London and New York, Oxford 

University Press, 1936. 



the EZVIPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 295 

as a pioneer of psychological and social science that Hume is 
chiefly remembered and most assured of immortality. He is 
remembered as the destroyer of that rationalistic tradition, 
which ever since the time of Parmenides, Plato, and Aristotle 
had wet-nursed the human intellect. It was a tradition which 
still constrained thought when Hume wrote, and which even 
today from certain strongholds seeks to assert its dominion. 
But because of Hume the iconoclast, a dogmatic rationalism 
can scarcely reign again. So soon as it asserts itself openly, it is 
met by the stem gaze and the unanswerable question of Hume, 
and it retires defeated. This is not to say that Hume rid us 
completely of dogmatism — there is still plenty of that in the 
world; but dogmatism exists henceforth by inadvertence, in 
disguise, or armed with bratal force. 

Dissatisfied with life as a shipping clerk, David Hume took 
his small competence to La Fleche, the little French town 
where Descartes had been educated; and there, after three 
years, still a young man in his middle twenties, he completed 
his first and greatest work, the Treatise on Human Nature. 
Note its title, and also its subtitle, which reads: an Attempt 
to introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral 
Subjects. We would not regard this book, today, as being 
primarily a study of human nature; we would discover in it no 
experiments; and we would say that only its less important 
chapters treat of morals. Its more important parts treat of 
causal relationship, a concept basic to every study of nature. 
By the “experimental method of reasoning” Hume meant, if 
we may judge him by his work, a science not committed to 
rationalistic prepossessions; and under “Moral Subjects” he 
included the whole range of human activity. 

There is no doubt that Hume’s initial purpose was to extend 
to the field of human behavior the sort of analysis so magnifi- 
cently applied by Newton to the field of physical nature. 
Newton seemed to have shown that all material change is 
explicable in terms of atomic particles, interacting according 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 


297 

diinks of knowledge as a pattern of ideas which is centered in 
a perceptual nucleus actually present, but supplemented by 
ideas recalled from memory. His purpose is to show how such 
recall occurs, and what sorts of conceptual knowledge it. gen- 
erates. 

It seems clear that we do call to mind from memory those 
ideas which are similar to the ideas now present to us. Our 
most basic and initial thought process is recognition, whereby 
present perception is supplemented by memory, i.e. by recalled 
earlier perception. Evidently there is among ideas this relation 
or associative bond of similarity, over and above the association 
of contiguity described above. Ideas are associated, Hume says, 
by contiguity and by resemblance. Thus an idea present in per- 
ception may call to mind a similar idea, earlier perceived; and 
thk earlier idea may bring along with it other ideas, contiguous 
with it in the earlier perception- You see Brown, you recognize 
him because your present perception is associated by resem- 
blance with your earlier perceptions of him, and you are now 
reminded of Brown’s dog which has usually accompanied him. 

This is the simple sort of analysis, known as associational 
psychology, by means of which Hume proposed to explain 
every mental process, and to develop the empirical doctrine 
which states that knowledge comes wholly from experience. It 
is generally considered today, among psychologists, to be 
faulty in its introspective method and inadequate in its con- 
stitutive hypothesis, although the facts of recall, which Hume 
explained as the result of “associations,” are evident enough. 
Contemporary empirical psychology either avoids introspec- 
tion altogether, or supplements it by a behavioristic study 
which places mental processes in the context of their bodily 
conditions and the external environment. Although Hume’s 
analysis undoubtedly assisted the progress of psychological 
science, it did this by elaborating an introspective psychology 
which finally made apparent its limitations and its nonempirical 
character. 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCSENCE 299 

psychological terms, became something else than psychology. 
The name “epistemology” has been used to designate this type 
of smdy, which seeks to understand the relations which hold 
between conceptual knowledge, immediate perception, and 
their objects. The chief philosophical value of Hume’s psycho- 
logical analysis lay in its concept of association, which allowed 
him to appreciate certain important relations among ideas— 
or among things — ^which had hitherto been neglected. 

The concept of association of ideas, like most of the other 
concepts of Hume’s psychology, came to him from Hobbes 
and Locke. Both of those thinkers had defined knowledge to 
be the result of a correct apprehension of relations among 
ideas. They had characterized true knowledge as a perception 
of relations intrinsic and proper to ideas, and indicated that 
error arises from the chance or contingent association of ideas 
in the mind. Thus the idea of triangle, they taught, is intrin- 
sically and intuitively related to the ideas of three intersecting 
straight lines, of three enclosed angles, etc., and one cannot 
entertain the first idea without the others. However, one may 
associate the idea of triangle widi a musical instrument of that 
shape, or with sandwiches which are often triangularly cut; 
and such associations are due merely to personal experience, 
and reveal nothing of the constitutive nature of triangles, musi- 
cal instruments, or sandwiches. Hume’s predecessors did not 
perceive — as some of his successors have not perceived — that 
in justifying the first sort of relationship as real and in defining 
the second sort, the associations, as the source of error, they 
were reestablishing philosophical rationalism, in spite of their 
philosophical conviction that knowledge comes only from 
experience. It was Hume’s genius to perceive the significance 
for our knowledge of nature of these chance or contingent 
associations. He had the intellectual audacity to make these 
associations, and not the “rational intuition” of “intrinsic and 
necessary relations,” the source and substance of natural knowl- 
edge. The whole of our natural knowledge, he taught, is only 



the empirical philosophy of modern science 301 

describes things less and less in terms of their visible appear- 
ances, and more and more by inference from their causal ac- 
tions and reactions. But what is causal action? Rationalism 
had consistently confused the concept of causation with the 
concept of substance, by supposing that the action of a thing 
is wholly due to the substantial nature of that thing. Rational 
insight into substances was accordingly supposed to carry with 
it a rational insight into causal necessities within nature. Hume 
perceived that in the new science, causal connection meant 
particular interaction among particular things, although the 
same sort of causal connection may recur again and again. 
What can we mean, he asks, by causal connection? Can we 
discover any necessary coimection, i.e. any rationally intuited 
relation, between a cause and its effect? He finds none; but 
he has a very simple explanation of causal connection in terms 
of associations. When A has been followed sufficiently often 
by B, he says, the appearance of A will induce in us the ex- 
pectation of B. The reason for this expectation is that A and B, 
having occurred often contiguously, are now firmly associated 
by contiguity. The reoccurrence of A arouses past memories 
of A, and these bring with them associated ideas of B, which 
we now expect to be realized again in perception along with A. 
The character of causal necessity which we impute to nature 
is really, it follows, a subjective character, resident in our- 
selves. The same sequence, repeated again and again, generates 
in us a habit of expectancy, such that the reoccurrence of A 
suggests the reoccurrence of B. Thus we come to believe that 
A necessitates B, independently of ourselves; and we proceed 
to a belief in universal natural necessity. Actually, however, 
we neither perceive nor understand any such necessity. So far 
as we know, A may recur without B, B may recur without 
A, AB may never occur again. We try to establish our faith 
in specific causal necessities by appealing to a universal princi- 
ple of necessity, which states that every event must have its 
cause; but this is arguing in a circle, because we have no 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SCIENCE 3O3 

we cannot reduce this relation between cause and effect to 
some intuitively known and rationally understood relation, but 
must accept it empirically and as we find it, then it follows 
that natural knowledge can do no more, in the last resort, than 
summarize observable fact. 

What are the consequences of Hume’s conclusions concern- 
ing natural knowledge? There are two sorts of consequence, 
respectively critical and constructive. The critical or destruc- 
tive consequences are the surer and the more important. They 
might be summed up as a recognition of the contingency of 
nature. To acknowledge the contingency of nature means that 
we acknowledge the impossibility of deducing the content or 
character of nature from anything we know prior to our ob- 
servation of nature. We must discover nature by observation 
and by study of observable fact, and we may not impose upon 
nature our preconception of what nature should be or must 
be. Since what we observe is always some particular situation, 
natural knowledge will consist of generalizations which sum- 
marize particular facts. And since our experience of particular 
fact is of necessity limited to what we or others have actually 
observed, our generalizations must be asserted modestly, and 
not exaggerated into definitions of “absolute reality.” All nat- 
ural knowledge is probable knowledge. Its probability may be 
very high, practically equivalent to certainty and theoretically 
close to certainty; but it cannot reach absolute certainty. For 
example, all human experience supports the belief that the 
earth will continue to turn on its axis, and that the sun will 
again rise tomorrow in the east. But we have no proof that the 
earth must continue so to turn; or if we could deduce this ro- 
tation from some general mechanical principle, then this 
principle in its turn would be indemonstrable and only em- 
pirical. Our widest, surest, and most basic knowledge of nature 
is still only a generalization from observed particular facts, 
and rests upon empirical evidence, i.e. upon observation. Even 
the most basic principles of natural science are of this sort; and 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SOENCE 305 

dieted and which had to be discovered by observatioiii Yet it 
is a very general and perhaps “universal” principle, and not 
itself a particular fact. All the principles of natural knowledge, 
Hume is saying, are of this sort. The whole of science, in- 
cluding its largest principles, is obtained from expefience; and 
it is subject, therefore, to change, modification, and growth. 

But what of the mathematical principles still incorporated 
in the Newtonian science? Are they not still rational, necessary, 
and universally applicable? Hume could not show that they are 
not; and it is evident that they embarrassed him, because they 
seemed to preserve a rational element in natural knowledge 
which he could not argue away. He dealt with the difiiculty 
in nvo ways. Sometimes he showed that the basic concepts of 
mathematics arise, just like any other concepts, as the result 
of associations among ideas; and this would imply that mathe- 
matical theory is no more absolute than other theory, e.g. physi- 
cal theory. At other times, he frankly recognizes that mathe- 
matical science arises from absolute rational axioms; but he 
assumes now that its principles do not apply perfectly to ob- 
servable fact, which is consequently still free to be what it 
will. Home’s honesty appears in this equivocal treatment of 
mathematics; for we know today that both of his two views, 
contradictory though they seem, are correct. A science like 
geometry includes two elements: an empirical element which is 
really descriptive but only probable, and a rational element 
which is certain, but not necessarily descriptive of anything 
in nature. 

Hume’s general conclusion was, then, that authentic knowl- 
edge must be identified with a natural science reaching general- 
izations possessed of greater or lesser probability, and that 
principles which are supposedly possessed of intuitive cer- 
tainty are on that very account suspect, and to be denied 
descriptive truth. This conclusion invalidated — ^with some 
reservation as regards mathematics — all so-called rational 
knowledge. Most emphatically it excluded aU rationalistic 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SQENCE 3O7 

should be remembered that Hume’s critical work is not preju- 
diced by the failure of Humian epistemology. It is the scientist, 
not the philosopher, who establishes the concepts of science. 

Hume’s statement of his conclusions was unnecessarily sub- 
jectivistic and skeptical. He was satisfied to say that causal 
knowledge, and therewith all natural knowledge, consists of 
habits of expectancy induced in us by past experience; and 
he did not further inquire — ^being prevented by his subjective 
psychological approach — ^into the implications of this state- 
ment. The statement implies, surely, that mental habits are 
effects of the more constant configurations of nature, continu- 
ously effective upon us in perception. The relation of knowl- 
edge to nature is at least that of effect to cause. This conclusion 
meets a difficulty which Kant was to exploit, since it conceives 
of a nature lying outside of experience, causing experience — 
and how, if all knowledge is derived from experience, should 
we know a nature which lies beyond experience? In the writer’s 
opinion, the problem is apparent rather than real. The empirical 
doctrine states that knowledge is derived from experience; but 
it does not exclude the realistic hypothesis that experience is 
the direct effect of a reality lying beyond the mind, and that 
experience consequently provides clues to the character of that 
reality. This hypothesis is a legitimate one, and one that is 
confixmed by all experience and analysis. 

Hume’s central thesis, that knowledge is the sum of mental 
habits induced by past impressions, is so broad and simple that 
it would cover animal as well as human psychology. This was 
its great value. It indicated certain characters of knowledge 
so general and so obvious that they had escaped attention. But 
it is also clear that Hume, in establishing the empirical basis 
of knowledge in observable fact, neglected the rationalistic 
elements which distinguish science from ordinary knowledge 
and animal habit. Mathematical reasoning and other sorts of 
reasoning which Hume would have called “metaphysical” 
have a most important auxiliary function in science. This much 



IHE EMPIBICAL PHOOSOPHY OP MODERN SCIENCE 309 

his lifetime, might be defended today as only a proper demand 
for intellectual independence in the pursuit of religious truth. 
With regard to revealed religion, Hume rejected miracles, 
along with whatever else cannot be brought into conformity 
with observable fact. But Hume’s attitude toward religion is 
that of the honest inquirer, not that of the atheist. He opened 
the way to an independent and creative study of religious 
factj and it is most to be regretted that the later centuries, 
which have turned Hume’s empiricism to good use in every 
other field, have tended to place religion outside of the intel- 
lectual pale, either as a truth too sacrosanct for impartial study 
and creative hypothesis, or as an error better left alone. It is 
a pusillanimous and ignoble compromise, ultimately destruc- 
tive of science and religion both, which has left to each of 
these two faiths one half of the mind and a peculiar social 
domain. 

Of next importance in Hume’s work, after his establishment 
of empirical science and method, was his application of this 
method to human and social fact. Hume did not follow Locke, 
who believed moral principles to be fixed and universal. He 
taught that moral knowledge too is derived from experience. 
But like many thinkers then and since, Hume did not suffi- 
dendy distinguish a psychological analysis of feelings, affec- 
tions, and emotions, as motives of human behavior, from moral 
theory. “Reason is and ought to be,” he wrote, “the slave of 
the passions.” In this revolutionary rejection of all earlier teach- 
ing, Hume attacked the divorce of “moral reason” from the 
emotional life of man. He recognized quite properly the de- 
pendence of action upon feeling, and the instrumental func- 
tion of thought ia analyzing and guiding our emotional re- 
sponses. But in his moral theory as elsewhere, he did less than 
justice to the rational element in man. The source of all moral 
distinctions and preferences, he taught, is ultimately the ex- 
perience and antidpation of pleasure and pain, these qualities 
attending all our states or “ideas.” Hume applied this hedonistic 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SOENCE JII 

Hume had ^vea more attentioa to this transition from “nat- 
ural” morality to “artificial” justice, and begun his ethical 
study with a consideration of government, he would have im- 
portantly amplified both his ethical and his political theory. 
But when he proceeds to his study of politics, he is once more 
the student of the natural growth of social institutions, intent 
upon showing how the natural impulses, widened by sympathy 
and strengthened by education, sufiice to explain the long de- 
velopment of legal and political institutions. He regards the 
concept of a social contract, by means of which Locke had 
established government upon the natural and inalienable rights 
of the individual, as a convenient but rationalistic fiction sym- 
bolizing the long development of organized society out of 
men’s natural needs and dispositions. He does not seek the 
principles which had implicitly determined this development. 
Hume left ethics in a confusion which can be removed only 
by an analysis superior to any attempted in the past. 

Thus there is a positive and a negative side to Hume; and 
we should see both sides clearly and estimate them objectively. 
The pofidve side is his empiricism and his naturalism. His em- 
piricism brought science back to its proper and necessary 
starting-point, which is observable particular fact, and cut 
down everything which might obstruct science by separating 
the scientist from observable facts. What most obstructed 
science was the retention, as absolute rational principles, of 
“metaphysical” concepts which were after all only the largest 
or mcst firmly established principles of Greek and medieval 
science. The Newtonian science had already broken away in 
some respects from these principles; and Hume, perceiving 
this, saw further that no scientific principle should or could 
be allow’ed such absolute authority. He quite properly con- 
cluded that all scientific principles which describe nature are 
but large generalizations from observed particular fact. In his 
application of this empirical theory of knowledge Hume be- 
comes a naturalist, which is to say that he finds in nature 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SQENCE 3I3 

worthily advancing an empirical rationalism, others desperately 
relinquishing the empirical insight of Hume and returning to 
rationalism; but Hume’s doctrines, too uncritically and liter- 
ally taken, have sometimes produced a sort of scientific ob- 
scurantism which only inverts the “fundamentalism” of the 
religious dogmatist. The earlier rationalism had its most popular 
expression in the concept of natural law. There are certain 
absolute principles, said the rationalistic philosopher, which 
must of necessity be applied in all scientific study, such appli- 
cation constituting science. There are certain absolute laws, 
said the popular version of this view, which all natural things 
must obey, as a result of their inclusion in the cosmos. Hume’s 
devastating criticism of rationalism has finally destroyed this 
faith in natural law; and there is no doubt that the old concept 
of natural law, which conceived material things to be neces- 
atated by such laws as that of gravitation, must be replaced 
by the insight that material things do m fact, but not by any 
observable necessity, conform to scientific formulas. Conse- 
quently, it is concluded, there is no law in nature, neither 
natural, nor moral, nor of any other sort. Thongs do what they 
please, without regard to any universal context or environ- 
ment; and it is simply an accident, with no implications of any 
kind, that things so conveniently conform in those ways which 
science successfully describes. The possibility of science, its 
existence and its continuous extension, it is concluded, carry 
simply no implications whatsoever regarding nature. 

Now this is an error as disastrous to science, and also to 
society, as was the earlier dogmatism. Science has not ceased 
to be rational in becoming empirical. It still makes demands 
upon nature, although these demands have emptied themselves 
of all save logical content; and the plasticity of fact to the 
demands of logic is still a character of fact, carrying implica- 
tions about the world at large. We will not develop this theme 
here; but we shall see, in our concluding chapters, that- the 
true effect of Hume’s criticism was not so much to invalidate 



THE EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN SOENCE 3I5 

age; for what was Rousseau’s rebellion, which unleashed 
hysterical revolution in France, compared with this rebellion 
which has challenged and still challenges every intellectual 
and social institution that cannot continue to justify its claim 
in terms of human experience? When Hume showed that the 
bond between cause and effect is no necessary bond, but a 
bond primarily of mental habit induced by past experience, and 
subject therefore to change in the light of new experience or 
experience better encompassed, he did no less than liberate 
human thought from human inertia. And in emancipating 
thought, he emancipated also action, to free at last the human 
race itself. Seldom, only occasionally as in his Dialogues Con- 
cerning Natural Religion, does that mighty imagination escape 
the rein of firm and even harsh restraint; but when it does, 
we realize that Hume liberated human thought in virtue of 
his own imaginative vision. He envisioned a nature that is free, 
moving, and intent, not to be deprived of its great leaping- 
times. It was a mystical adoration of natural freedom, of 
liberty in all nature, that moved Hume to cut those intellectual 
bonds which had confined the thought of man through earlier 
time. 


Notes for Further Reading 

1. Hume, D., A Treatise on Human Nature, ed. Green and Grose. 

London and New York, Longmans, Green and Company, 
1874. 

2. Works, ed. Green and Grose. London and New York, 

Longmans, Green and Company, 1874. 

3. A Treatise on Human Nature, ed. Selby-Bigge. London 

and New York, Oxford University Press, 1903. 

4. The Engines, ed. Selby-Bigge. Oxford, The Claren- 

don Press, 1894. 

5. Hendel, C. W., Hume: Selections. New York, Charles Scrib- 

ner’s Sons, 1927. 

6. Green, T. H., “Introduction to Hume,” Treatise on Human 

Nature, ed. Green and Grose. London and New York, 
Longmans, Green and Company, 1874. A critical study. 



17 THE REVIVAL OF 

POLITICAL ABSOLUTISM 


In the writings of locke, Berkeley, and hume 
we see the development of an empirical philosophy 
which in its theoretical and practical teachings expresses the 
outlook most characteristic of modem man. It is emphatically 
a liberal or libertarian philosophy. In its study of science it 
elevates particular fact, which is an apprehension of individual 
being, into the chief criterion of truth. In its moral and political 
teaching, it makes the human individual the source and seat of 
authority, and the welfare of individuals die objective of 
government. 

TThis empirical and democratic development has proceeded 
freely and unobstructed chiefly in the English-speaking world, 
i.e. in Britain and America. It has not, generally speaking, 
characterized the thought and practice of continental Europe. 
European thought has remained bound by rationalistic habits 
long induced by medieval scholasticism, and never completely 
renounced; and European governments have been for the most 
part feudal, monarchical, or otherwise absolutistic. The in- 
tellectual and political collapse of continental Europe in our 
century is the consequence of this failure to advance from ab- 

317 



THE REVIVAL OF POLIHCAL ABSOLUTISM 3I9 

absolutism; and the forms of political absolutism so generated 
are many and diverse. 

In Britain and America, the movement to democracy was 
initiated by the first English revolution, which resisted the 
violence done by an absolute monarch to his subjects’ reUgious 
convictions; and this first revolution gave to all the later politi- 
cal development a religious significance and support. On the 
continent of Europe, the revolutionary movement proceeded 
under different auspices to a different outcome. The Girtesian 
philosophy, in spite of the idealistic efforts of such men as 
Spinoza and Leibniz, tended to become a physicalism or ma- 
terialism which sees in existent reality only a universal physical 
mechanism. The Cartesian concept of natural science was 
usually the resource of progressive thinkers who desired to 
carry society out of medieval darkness into truth, and to strike 
off feudal shackles which were clamped ever more oppressively 
upon continental peoples, the more the inadequacy and in- 
justice of feudal forms became apparent. In France, the ma- 
terialistic tendencies of Cartesianism were further strengthened 
as a result of the ecclesiastical support given to the monarchy, 
which bought this support by extending protection and privi- 
lege to the established clergy. The reform movement became 
anticlerical, and from anticlericalism it was easy to proceed to 
materialism and atheism. The result was a confusion of pro- 
gxesave and religious currents which has defeated political 
progress on the continent of Europe from that day to the 
present. The struggle between progresave and conservative 
factions became extraordinarily bitter, and revolution became 
unnecessarily bloody, cruel, and the cause of social vendetta. 

At first, the Enlightened intellectuals who led the party of 
reform gave some recognition to religious faith. Voltaire, 
Helverius, and other liberal thinkers professed Deism, a view 
which held God to have created the world, but which rejected 
the conception of revealed religion that a divine providence 
works in or upon man at all times. According to the Deist, 



THE REVIVAL OF POLITICAL ABSOLUTISM 


3ZI 

beyond the empirical evidence, and in some respects contra- 
dicts that evidence. It would seem, for example, that just as 
physical theory was importantly modified when it was extended 
to cover the analysis of chemical phenomena, so it will again 
be modified when it is extended to cover organic and mental 
phenomena. A physical science developed to the point where 
it could be made to comprehend all fact whatsoever would 
explain the phenomena of human morality and religion; and 
so comprehensive a science would need to distinguish, and 
could not reduce to a common physical level, the activities 
of moral man, of sensitive animals, and of ina nimate bodies. 

In France, rationalistic thought delivered itself of its absolu- 
tistic political implications in the teachings of Jean Jacques 
Rousseau (1712-1778), whose writings were perhaps the chief 
inspiration of the leaders of the French revolution. Rousseau 
was an unhappy, neurotic, expatriated Swiss, whose gift of im- 
petuous eloquence made him the spokesman of oppressed and 
unhappy France. His chief political work, Le Contrat Social, 
incited the French people, as later it incited other peoples, to 
revolt against their feudal and monarchical forms of govern- 
ment. But Rousseau’s book also provided the concept upon 
which was established the absolutistic political theory of the 
centuries which followed. 

The most distinctive feature of Rousseau’s political teaching 
is this concept of the general •will, by means of which he in- 
tended to reconcile individual freedom with absolute state 
power. The political unit should be small enough, he taught, 
to allow its citizens to meet together in general assembly, to 
participate individually in debate, and to reach their decisions 
by majority vote. But what is it in the majority vote that car- 
ries authority over aU the members of the community? The 
majority vote has this authority, Rousseau says, because it ex- 
presses the general 'will. This is the will of the community as 
a whole, shared by all citizens including even those who voted 
against the measure. The majority vote expresses the “essence” 



THE REVIVAL OF POLITICAL ABSOLUTISM 323 

it rrmst have a umversal and compelling force ... The social 
compact gives the body politic ahsolzite povser over dl its 
members ... The voice of the people is the voice of God” 

This is very far, we should insist, from the political theory 
upon which our own democracy is established. We agree with 
Rousseau that the ballot is the fairest and most expedient means 
of determining public opinion and electing an administration; 
but we do not believe with Rousseau that the use of this 
method requires us ever to renounce our indmdual judgment, 
and to accept the vote of a majority as the voice of our “real” 
conscience. If an Aryan majority should vote to exterminate 
a non-Aryan minority, if a white majority should vote to 
enslave a Negro minority — ^is that the voice of God? It is 
not Rousseau’s faith out of which grew our American institu- 
tions. These were established to define and to limit the powers 
of the state, to protect minorities, and to place moral sanctions 
wholly and forever in the individual conscience. But Rousseau’s 
concept of the general will was the faith out of which must 
grow, steadily as the decades pass, absolutism such as we see 
growing in our world today. We must know that there is no 
general will. There are only individual wills. 

Several things con^ired to disguise from Rousseau the ab- 
solutism implicit in his theory, or to reconcile him with it. He 
proposed to limit the size of the state so radically that no estab- 
lished government, possessed of permanent power, would be 
needed. The whole ccwnmunity could in this case gather in 
general assembly to exercise its political responsibilities; and 
this would tend to prevent the alienation of political power 
from individual citizens to some well-entrenched caucus or 
political machine. But the proposal to limit states to small 
townships is wholly impracticable. The irresistible movement 
of civilized society is toward states of continental size, exerting 
highly concentrated power. It is the more important therefore 
to define governmental powers, and to secure the principle of 
individual and minority rights. In the large modern state it is 



THE REVIVAL OF POLITICAL ABSOLXmSM 


325 

political revolt that was to incite a no less violent reaction; and 
the path of social progress in France became tortuous and 
difficult. 

Like the C5nnics and Cyrenaics of ruined Greece, Rousseau 
sought refuge from social ills in the ideal of the “natural man,” 
emancipated from all social convention and completely good 
in his original nature; but where the Greek reformer identified 
this original nature with reason, Rousseau identified it with 
feeling or sentiment. This appeal to feeling made him a prophet 
of romanticism, and one of the forerunners of the later “revolt 
against reason.” Thus Rousseau’s social rebellion initially in- 
dicted the whole development of civilization, with all of its 
moral and intellectual outcome. He held up the “noble savage” 
as the proper ideal of a humanity freed from the corruptions 
and diseases of civilization. (This ideal was of course a sheer 
fiction. Primitive or “savage” man is far more bound than are 
we by tabu and social convention, and the history of civiliza- 
tion is that of a progressive emancipation of the individual; 
but it was a fiction giving forceful expression to a revolt against 
moral and intellectual restraint which has moved underneath all 
later European life, and which finally broke through the surface 
of moral “convention” to perpetrate the massacres and brutalities 
of the last three decades.) By replacing the natural and spon- 
taneous relations among men with a wholly artificial structure, 
Rousseau taught, civilization induces an unhealthy growth in 
which man grows progressively more corrupt. With his natural 
sentiments deformed by unhealthy arts, and with his native 
intelligence destroyed by a cold and artificial intellectualism, 
man developed an industrial economy which divided society 
into the wealthy and the poverty-stricken, and then estab- 
lished a tyrannous state which sanctified and perpetuated eco- 
nomic injustice as political “justice.” Civilization and the in- 
tellect, he concluded, are all our woe, our progress is truly a 
progressive decay, and health is to be regained only by sweep- 
ing out of existence the whole corrupted fabric of civilized 



THE REVIVAL OF POLITICAL ABSOLUTISM 327 

the theas which is fundamental to “progressive education” to- 
day. Its attack upon a too formal education, and its concern 
for the vital development of the individual child, have never 
ceased to be provocative of educational reform. There is moral 
and religious significance in its rejection of the doctrine of 
original sin, a tenet of the Calvinistic faith which originated in 
Rousseau’s birthplace, Geneva. Yet this pedagogical theory, like 
most of Rousseau’s thought, is equivocal. To remove children 
wholly from adult influence, say by letting them grow up to- 
gether in the woods, would be to produce something neither 
animal nor human, and nothing like what Rousseau envisaged 
as “the natural man.” Any and every educatio nal program, 
whether it be progressive or formal, Wl provide an environ- 
ment which is stimulating in some ways and restraining in 
others, and which will importantly condition the child’s de- 
velopment. 

What Rousseau and the progressive educator really pro- 
pose, therefore, is to study the child as a growing organism 
and as a unique individual, and on the basis of this understand- 
ing to provide stimulation and opportunity adapted to the 
individual child; and such education may go far beyond that 
casually provided by the adult society which is the child’s en- 
vironment A pedagogy of this sort will indeed be more effec- 
tive, and determine the character and personality of the pupil 
much more deeply and strongly, than a formal and stereotyped 
education. Such education requires, of course, a more intimate 
understanding and closer care of the individual child by the 
educator, with more effective direction of the child’s develop- 
ment. The result of such education will depend almost wholly 
upon the character and ideals of the educator. A liberal educa- 
tor will produce liberals, a revolutionary will produce rebels, 
and a reactionary will produce reactionaries. The progressive 
educator is self-deceived, unless he is of the sort that just turns 
his pupils out to grass, if he thinks of his pupils’ development 
as in some peculiar way a natural growth. He himself, with 



THE REVIVAL OF POLITICAL ABSOLUTISM 329 

whole people; and this ascription of absolute moral authority 
to one part of society, that expressing its “will,” necessarily 
requires the extension to that part of an absolute authority 
recognizing no limits to government. A group or class so em- 
powered could never be ’ustifiably nor successfully challenged. 
The town meeting can no longer be our government. The 
democratic spirit of the town meeting had to be built into 
the Constimtion of the United States, setting limits to govern- 
ment in the interests of individual liberty. 

It should be remarked that the political theory of Rousseau 
has nowhere, neither in France nor elsewhere, supported a 
stable and healthy democratic society. To affirm that men are 
basically good is not to affirm that any and every majority is 
necessarily and absolutely right, so that not to accept its de- 
cision is to convict oneself of immorality. If there is a general 
will, why must it locate itself in a given majority? Why might 
it not locate itself in an intelligent, specially trained, intensely 
patriotic, or hereditarily privileged minority? The absolutists 
seized upon Rousseau’s concept, and discovered the general 
will to reside in aristocratic national tradition (Burke), in a 
feudal monarchy (Hegel), in racial or national exclusiveness 
(Fichte), in the sheer will to power (Nietzsche), in imperial 
ambition (Mussolini), in a divine emperor (Japan), in the 
proletariat (Marx and Lenin.) The doctrine is just what de- 
mocracy must and does reject. Constitutional democracy se- 
cures the absolute rights of all individuals, allowing to govern- 
ment only limited and delegated powers. Political absolutism 
secures absolute power to some group, ostensibly the vehicle 
of the “general will,” and therefore identified with “the state.” 
For democracy there is no state or states, there are only 
individuals and their governments. 

Notes for Further Reading 

I. Hibben, J. G., Philosophy of the Enlightenment. New York, 
Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1910. 



18 


KANT: CAN RATIONALISM AND 
EMPIRICISM BE RECONCILED? 


w HAVE NOW SEEN THE TWO OPPOSED INTER- 

pretadons of modern science. Descartes and his suc- 
cessors perpetuate the mjonalistic iptei^retadon in a modified 
and more exacting form. They hold tiiat reason is equipped 
with certain absolute principles or concepts which apply un- 
failingly and of necessity to every detail of particular fact- 
Natiixal science accordingly is just the continued application 
to existent fact of these at^lute principles defining the ultimate 
structure of the universe. The empiricists, on the contrary, in- 
sist that natur^UIrQOwri^dge is- dmved from experience, and 
conasts of empirical generalisations summarizing observed par- 
ticular facts. Their criticism of rationalism culminates in 
Hume, who concludes that even the best-established principles 
of natural science fall short of absolute certainty, and possess 
only a high probability as habits of mind determined by past 
experience. 

It would seem that neither of these opposed views can be 
completely discounted. Rationalism failed to explain such 
principles as the law of gravitation, which seems to be uni- 
versal in scope although it is not a self-evident or rational 


33 * 



KANT 


333 

temporary thought. K we will return to the spirit or intention 
of Kant, while renouncing his false premises, we shall succeed 
where he failed. We shall reach a conception at once rational 
and empirical, able to embrace the largest insights of past 
philosophy. 

Immmuel Kant (1724-1804) lived the uneventful life of a 
professor at the remote University of Konigsberg in northern 
Prussia. He had some Scottish ancestry, awareness of which 
may have made him more susceptible to Hume. His family 
was Pietist, a fervent sect similar to our Quakers. His education 
was of the very formal, scholastic sort then prevalent in Ger- 
many. This education gave him a horrendous vocabulary; but 
it strengthened his conviction in the integrity of the largest 
intellectual tradidon of western thought, that which came from 
Greek antiquity. 

The philosophy imbibed by Kant in his school education 
consisted chiefly of a scholasticized version of Leibniz; and it 
is evident from Kant’s Inaugural Dissertation that this study 
had already made him aware of certain difficulties in the ra- 
tionalistic philosophy. He had learned from Leibniz that the 
general principles of reason could never disclose anything con- 
cerning the location in space and time of a given event. Even 
if we were to suppose all of the general principles of physical 
science to be given to us with the reason, these principles 
would never necessitate the existence of a solar system, with a 
son having just this mass and just so many planets. The general 
laws of matter would never reveal how matter is distributed 
in space and time. This meant, Kant saw, that aU acmal knowl- 
edge requires experience, and that the world in its concrete 
content is a contingent world. But it was the study of Hume, 
Kant tells us himself, that “awoke him from his dogmatic 
slumber.” Kant was the first, and remains one of the few, to 
grasp the full implication of Hume’s criticism; and it was be- 
cause he comprehended Hume’s teaching that he realized its 
inadequacy as a description of human knowledge, and set him - 



KANT 


335 

reacting according to known mechanical laws. Kant did 
not share the view of the earlier empiricists that scien- 
tific method may be applied to human nature, to produce 
a science of human behavior. In his conception of science, he 
remained Cartesian and dualistic. There is physical nature, sub- 
ject to mechanical law; and there is the human mind, which 
faces and knows a physical nature of which it is no part. 
Leibniz had written, in a late work critical of the empiricism 
of Locke: “Yes, everything in the mind is derived from ex- 
perience — except the intellect itself!” Kant subscribed to this 
view. The mind is not merely a part of nature. It has its own 
constitution and its peculiar sort of activity; and this intellectual 
constitution enters into all our knowledge. Kant’s problem was 
to show how the intellect with its fixed principles combines 
with the empirical material provided by the senses, in such a 
way as to do violence to neither element. It is dear, he believed, 
that the most basic intellectual principles caimot be derived 
from experience. They are and remain authoritative, and to 
deny their authority is simply to end in skepticism. Hume 
might say that there is no necessary causal connection in nature, 
that a stone flung into the air might just as easily — ^that is, for 
aught we know — ^fly up to the moon as sink to earth. But sup- 
pose that just one stone, so flung, did not fall to earth — ^would 
not the sdentist look for a cause? Would he not reclassify 
stones into gravitating and nongravitating substances, and per- 
sistently seek until he had found the deeper law, or the under- 
lying natural necessity, which rules botW* Science aflSrms causal 
determination in nature; it does not merely aflBrm a subjective 
determination of human expectancies. Sdence has never had 
to retract this demand, nor could it retract the demand with- 
out committing suicide. Not to require causal connection in 
nature would be to suppose that anything, or nothing, may 
cause an)rthing. It was in the interests of empirical science it- 
self, we should see, that Kant took issue with Hume. 

So Kant will establish empirical science and philosophy in a 



KANT 


337 

this is the sort of proposition that could be wrong, and is estab- 
lished only by empirical evidence, i.e. by observation or ex- 
periment. 

Mathematical propositions, then, are a priori and rational; 
but do they constitute real knowledge, or are they, as the 
empiricists implied, only a knowledge of words or ideas? Kant 
recognized that there are such purely nominal definitions, 
merely disclosing what is meant by a word. Thus the sentence 
“a dog is an animal” is necessarily true, but it is true only be- 
cause the word “dog” means a certain sort of animal, and what 
is not an animal could therefore not be called a “dog.” Such 
propositions E^nt calls analytic, because they only analyze the 
meanings of words, and do not necessarily tell us anything 
about the world. “Angels are bodiless spirits” is a perfectly 
good analytic proposition, because it correctly defines “angels”; 
but it tells us nothing about the world if we have no empirical 
evidence that angek exist. If the propositions of mathematics 
are of this? analytic sort, their absoluteness is of litde impor- 
tance, since they need describe nothing in the world. (This 
was Berkeley's view, and at times Hume’s.) But Kant holds 
mathematical propositions to be synthetic. They cannot be 
reduced to nominal definitions, he says, because they do more 
than state the meanings of words. The word “triangle,” for 
example, may necessarily mean three intersecting lines; but 
it does not logically imply that the angles of a triangle sum up 
to i8o°. One might know the meaning of “triangle” without 
knowing this. Yet everyone believed, when Kant wrote, that 
a triangle necessarily contains angles to the sum of i8o°. Thus 
Kant reaches his conclusion that the propositions of mathe- 
matics are at once a priori and synthetic. They are necessary, 
certain, absolute, universal in their truth; and yet they con- 
stitute a knowledge of fact, i.e. of things, and not merely a 
knowledge of words and their meanings. 

How, Kant asks, is such a priori synthetic knowledge possi- 
ble? How can we have an intuition into the universal, absolute, 



KANT 


339 

do in mathematics. They see numbers, but do not count and 
name them. 

The second level of mind is built upon the first. It produces 
an order defined in the categories of the understanding, such 
as relationship, causation, substance, etc. These categories play 
into all our ordinary thinking; but they are most consistently 
applied in science, which carries further the modes of thinking 
used in common sense. These constitutional forms should not 
be thought of as passive or inert. They are the forms of our 
conscious activity in perception and intellection. They are 
fixed and definable ways of organizing, ordering, and cata- 
loguing sensations. 

But why, and by what right, does the mind organize its sen- 
sations first into temporal succession and spatial order, and 
then into the more complicated and specific spatiotemporai 
patterns we call “causal processes,” “substances,” etc.? The 
librarian, cataloguing his books as they arrive, follows a general 
plan of some specific sort. He may catalogue them alphabeti- 
cally, or according to the date of their publication, or by their 
subject matter, or in some complicated way using all of these 
orders. What plan does the mind follow? Its ultimate aim, 
Kant says, is 'unity, a single all-comprehensive ^stem. Evi- 
dently, the sort of pattern that results will be determined in 
some degree by the sort of sensory material that is to be or- 
ganized; and we can accordingly specify, in some degree, the 
sort of pattern that is reached. For example, all of our sensa- 
tions whatsoever belong in the time-order; but only some of 
them enter into the ^ace-order, while others do not. Those 
which are spatially ordered we attribute to external reality; 
and our effort to organize these iuto unity is guided by our 
idea of a completed world. We never actually complete this 
oiganizadon, so that the nnorld remains only an ided, always 
in the making. Those sensations which cannot be ^atialized 
Kant attributes to our internal reality; and these are organized 
in view of an idea or ideal of the self, which again, of course, 



KANT 


341 

perception, because perception is composed of sensations so 
ordered. Similarly, we may be sure that every perceived event 
will have its determinate causes and effects, and take its place 
in the physical order revealed by science. Science is established, 
consequently, upon a solid basis of rational and necessary 
truth. Its basic categories are beyond dispute. 

However, there are important negative consequences flowing 
from Kant’s study. These rational principles are really princi- 
ples of mental procedure. We caimot change them, because 
they are constitutive of thought; yet they do not, as they 
stand, describe anything outside of the mind. They cannot be 
called “principles of absolute being.” They become descriptive 
only when they are actually applied in the organization of 
sensory material. Our knowledge stretches, therefore, only as 
far as our experience extends, or perhaps as far as human 
experience extends, if we may believe what others have seen. 
It follows that although the principles are universal and abso- 
lute, the knowledge which they produce is not so, because it 
extends only as far as a limited human experience. “Concepts 
without percepts are empty, percepts without concepts are 
blind,” wrote Kant in a justly famous phrase. 

Kant seems to have reached his objective, which was to 
reconcile the apparently opposed claims of rationalism and 
empiricism. The rationalist is correct in his defense of absolute 
principles, but wrong in his claim to absolute knowledge. The 
empiricist is right in claiming that knowledge derives from 
experience, but wrong when he denies absolute principles. The 
trath is, Kant holds, that we have actual knowledge when the 
material provided by experience is properly organized by 
means of absolute principles — and only then. Knowledge is 
more than a summary of past experience; but it is less than an 
insight into universal being. Einowledge is the integration of 
a lirated experience in the direction of an ideal of unity whi^h 
lies beyond experience. If we could integrate all experience, 
we might achieve this ideal, and know absolute being; but 



KANT 


343 

is infinite in time and space, yet also finitej that nature had a 
first cause or beginning, yet that every beginning had its earlier 
cause; etc. The principles of reason in this way themselves 
prohibit or rather protest their abuse. They are regulative prin- 
ciples, not descriptive truths. They work well so long as we 
use them in the description of some limited part of nature, 
i.e. apply them in the analysis of particular fact. But they col- 
lapse when we try to make them the pillars of a knowledge of 
absolute, universal being. The reason, as Locke saw, has its 
inherent limits. It is the indispensable servant of empirical 
science; but it is useless when divorced from ejtperience, as it 
is divorced in all metaphysics. 

But at this point we must ask: Do- we not begin here to 
undermine the power or validity of empirical science, as well 
as that of rationalistic metaphysics? Should we not suspect that 
principles which collapse when we work t^m too hard are 
less than reliable even where they seem tOfUerve well? How do 
we know that the regulative, organizing pifinciples of the mind 
give us knowledge of reality when we apply them circum- 
spectly, in actual experience? We cannot know, Kant replies, 
r/x nsorld that appears to usiin perception, and that is de- 
scribed by empirical science, is a phenoTnenal world. It is some- 
thing we ourselves construct; and since we can never get out of 
■ourselves, to see the world without looking at it and to know 
the world without thinking it, we can never know the relation 
of our knowledge to that nommnd reality which is reality-in- 
itself. We are like a person who is given a few of the 
fragmentary words or syllables which, in their totality, com- 
pose a story, and who is challenged to reconstruct the story. 
We know certain rules of composition, and we do our best; but 
there is no one who knows the original story, to tell us how 
nearly we are reproducing it. Is our version at all creditable? 
Or, dreadful thought, is there no original? Do we compose only 
our own dream? Is science reconstruction of the real, or is it 
merely a human construction or artifact? 



BJcsr 


345 

the phenomenal fire merely. The appearance of fire we could 
csrtinguish merely by closing our eyes or moving elsewhere. 
Thus we move in a real world, we act upon real things, yet 
we see and know only appearances! And what is more, we 
know the difference between extinguishing the fire itself, and 
removing its appearance! Somehow, therefore, we do distin- 
guish between phenomena and noumena; and this involves 
knowledge of both. The positivistic doctrine, moreover, be- 
comes immoral when it is applied to living organisms. We must 
believe that a dog’s yelp indicates real pain in the dog, not 
merely the phenomenon in our minds. We must believe that 
our s}.TTipathy helps a real person to forget a real sorrow. As 
Kant will recognize in his study of morality, moral insight must 
penetrate through appearance and reach reality, if moral judg- 
ments are to be valid. But moral judgments are conditioned by 
factual judgments, and are valid only if these are true. 

We may conclude, perhaps, that Kant’s study of knowledge 
reveals its own failme by thus issuing in phenomenalism. We 
may not buy our faith in science at so high a price. But Kant’s 
study is valuable even in its failure. It has revealed to what 
degree sdenoe is an elaborate edifice, constructed by the mind. 
Kant, following the empiricists, has invalidated the old naive 
realism which took knowledge to be a direct reflection of an 
external reality in the eye or mind. Further, he has shown that 
the effort to retain universal rational principles, at least if we 
accept also the empirical view that natural knowledge comes 
from experience, leads to a new sort of skepticism, namely 
phenomenalism. It would seem that any regrilative principle 
which is imposed by the mind upon experience, and which in- 
troduces into experience its own structure, must have this out- 
come. To avoid this skeptical outcome, we would need regula- 
tive principles which merely open the mind to what lies outside 
of the mind. To see, we must open our eyes. To know, we 
must open our minds. What would such principles be, requiring 
us to open eyes and mind? 



KANT 


347 

reappeais in the Kantian dualism of phenomenon and non- 
mencm, appearance and reality. 

These difEculties or inadequacies in the Kantian philosophy 
were apparent in Kant’s day, not least to Kant hunself; but 
they were inescapable then, and for long afterwards. Once we 
suppose that certain principles, for instance those of mathe- 
matics, are at once absolute or rational and necessarily descrip- 
tive of the world, we are caught in Kant’s dilemma and im- 
pelled toward Kant’s conclusions. The great value of Kant’s 
philosophy is first to have clearly defined, m its definition of 
a priori synthetic propositions, the essential core of rational- 
ism; and then to have shovm the inevitable consequences of 
rationalism, in phenomenalism or positivism. No one has shed 
so much light upon the intellectual process, with its rational 
and empirical elements and their relationship, as did Klant. 

But today this foundation of a priori synthetic knowledge, 
upon which Kant established his whole study, no longer exists. 
Within the twentieth century, advances in logic, mathematics, 
and physical science have shifted the weight of evidence against 
Kant’s basic premise stating that the propositions of mathe- 
matics are a priori yet ^nthetic. Physicists now treat geo- 
metrical theories as physicd hypotheses, modifying them as re- 
quired by the observed facts; and this means that geometrical 
propositions are synthedc or descriptive of fact, but not abso- 
lute nor a priori. Logicians, on the other hand, have shown that 
the axioms of arithmedc may be regarded as analydc proposi- 
dons which merely define the uses or meanings of symbols. 
Thus the evidence today no longer supports the premises upon 
which Kant's study was based. When Kant wrote, all extant 
evidence supported his belief in the existence of a priori syn- 
thetic propositions. Today, if this belief is not conclusively 
falsified, it is at least shown to be dubious and precarious. Th^ 
shift of evidence in Kant’s disfavor does not imply that Kant 
was mistaken in his acknowledgment of a rational elf^rnen t in 



KANT 


349 


ciples, had believed in absolute moral principles. Kant finds no 
a priori and s%'nthet:c moral truths, corresponding to those of 
mathematics in science. Because he had established all scientific 
knowledge upon this basis of a priori and synthetic principles, 
he is compelled to deny the possibility of every sort of moral 
science, even or especially an empirical moral science such as 
the utilitarians pursued. 

WTiat then is moral insight, if there is neither a rational 
science establishing absolute moral principles, nor an empirical 
science deriving moral knowledge from experience? Is moral 
judgment arbitrary and irrational? No, Kant replies; it is, on 
the contrary, the only sort of judgment that might be called 
absolute and wholly rational. Moral judgment, Kant believes, 
penetrates through the curtain of phenomena which veils us 
from reality-in-itself, and reaUy gra^s, in full and naked imme- 
diacy, its noumenal object in reality. Kant is recognizing here 
that although we may fail to describe ultimate being in con- 
cepraal formulas, we are ourselves real and ultimate in our 
movement and conduct. Girrect moral judgment is therefore 
right conduct, intelligent practice. An act is right, Kant be- 
lieves, if it is motivated wholly by good will; and in our con- 
science we have awareness of our motives. We cannot see into 
other hearts, and know their motives; and so we do well not to 
judge others’ conduct. W’hen we are motivated by good will, 
Kant implies, we have true insight into the individual atuadon 
upon which we act. G>nscience is a sort of knowledge; but 
because it is an individual awareness of a unique particular 
situation, it does not provide general principles nor moral 
theories. What has been prescribed as general precept and 
moral code, Kant says, truly amounts only to a classification of 
the material situations in wHch the moral drama plays. We may 
speak of cases of honesty or dishonesty, kindness or cruelty, 
etc. But what makes an act honest or dishonest, kind or 
cruel, is its activation of an individual moral insight which is 
never duplicated. The noumenal reality which appears in the 



KAinr 


351 

Kant’s moral doctrine has been much debated since he pre- 
sented it to the world, some accusing it of being empty, others 
proceeding to infer from it a whole code of moral precepts. 
In the writer’s opinion, such debate is today out of place. 
Kant’s formulation of moral doctrine was based upon the con- 
clusions of the first Critique-^ and these conclusions required 
the absolute separation of judgments of fact from moral judg- 
ments. But we no longer accept the assumptions, and therefore 
we escape the conclusions, of the first Critique. However, Kant’s 
doctrine is far from being empty. It presupposes a plurahty of 
persons or human individuals, each an end or ultimate value in 
himself, and each possessed of individual rights and of respon- 
sibility for aU other individuals. It is, in short, the moral theory 
of Locke, upon which was established democratic society; and 
the writer confesses that he has found no other doctrine upon 
which democratic justice can be established. 

It is in truth a metaphysical doctrine, affirming that human 
beings are ultimate, irreducible, plural, and individual — or it 
would be a metaphysical doctrine, if this irredudbly individ- 
ualistic pattern of human nature were extended to all of nature 
and made universal. 

If Kant’s ethical doctrine provided the indispensable founda- 
tion of democratic practice, Kant’s polifical theory falls short 
of what we might reasonably expect from him. It is true that 
he explicitly locates moral responsibility in ihe individuaL and 
denies that the state has an intrinsic value aud authority; yet 
these explicit statements are prejudiced by the admission fbar 
the state is a necessary condition of moral conduct and indi- 
vidual freedom. This view would ultimately compel us to allow 
to the state an unquestionable and absolute authority. This con- 
ception, we have seen, goes back to Rousseau and Hobbes, 
who also conceived the state to be the necessary source of all 
morality. It is not consistent with the Kantian ethics, which 
defines the human individual as a moral being, independent 
of any political organization. Truer to his ethical insight is 



KANT 


353 

science becomes ineifable, and can express itself only in action. 
Kno'wing and doing must proceed in different worlds. Science 
and morality face opposite ways, 

Kant, it seemed, had wholly sundered science and morality. 
Yet in his first Critique, Kant had taught that our knowledge 
of the world and our knowledge of the self should ultimately 
be brought together in a comprehensive syntheas of experi- 
ence, under the regulation of the Idea of God. In his third 
and last Critique he attempted this synthesis. 

TTie Critique of Judg}»ent should have been the crown of 
tjhi’.cscphical study and the keystone of his great 
architecrcnic; b-r :r was in fact a supreme and tragic failure. 
All of its great enterprises tail off into negative conclusions. 
Kant pays in this book the full price of the errors of the earlier 
Critiques. And yet, through this explicit failure, there shines 
like a great promise the suggestion of what the book would 
have been if it had succeeded. Here, as always, Kant’s genius 
lay in his grasp of the speculative problem and the right ap- 
proach to it, and not in his attempted solution of it; and in this 
third Critique, the problem attacked is the last, most ultimate 
of all problems, namely the relation of human life with its 
effort, its conscience, and its consciousness, to the world en- 
vironing and generating that life. 

Let us first appreciate the Critique of Judgment in its grand 
plan; and only then consider why the vast projection failed! 
The book proposed what seemed impossible, a synthesis of the 
first two Critiques bringing together the two domains of scien- 
tific and moral cognition, which had there been defined in such 
a way as to exclude each other. With the simplicity character- 
istic of genius, Kant points out that the only likeness between a 
scientific judgment and a moral judgment is that both are 
judgments. If we knew, therefore, what is involved in any act 
of judgment even as such, we should have a clue to the con- 
nection between science and morality. What, he asks, are the 
presuppositions of any and every judgment? 



KANT 355 

lime; and in works of art, he distinguishes talent from genius 
and technical facility from aesthetic insight. 

What more can one say concerning this character of aes- 
thetic value or beauty? What is its claim upon us? It does not 
incite, but rather discourages, intellectual analysis and formal 
classification. We feel that the beautiful object is consummate, 
that it fulfils itself and beggars description. It makes and meets 
a claim, it realizes a need which is not ours but its own. All 
beauty, Kant concludes, is apprehension of some realization of 
individual being. We love the thing for its own sake, not for 
our sake. This quality of beauty, this mark of individual self- 
realkation, seems to be wholly objective and independent of 
our minds. 

At the root of all judgment whatsoever lies this aesthetic 
apprehension of objective individual being; and presumably 
all science and all morality, in their movements to comprehend 
experience and enrich judgment, do no more than integrate or 
S}’T:thcsize this basic and primary aesthetic aspect of reality. 
Nor does there seem any Umit within experience to this aes- 
thetic quality. Nature is beautiful in our widest percepdon of it, 
for example in the night sky with its illimitable distances. Does 
all scientific and moral conprehension of fact only formulate 
our aesthetic apprehensicai of reality? Can we say that nature at 
large realizes itself, and thus manifests purpose and aim? Do 
science and moral insight conjoin, to reach this final insight 
into a reality which in its largest design, even as in its most 
particular detail, reveals a single purposive intelligence? This 
would indeed make science and morality consummate, by 
shovting them to be respectively the theory and the practice of 
a religious apprehension of universal being. 

This is the sort of synthesis that is suggested in the third 
Critique-, but the plan is not carried out, because at each step 
some obstacle arises to prevent its advance. Thus Kant will not 
allow cognitive status to aesthetic insight, because he finds no 
a priori aesthetic principles regulating aesthetic judgment. W^e 



KANT 


357 

mechanical clock serves tJie purpose of its maker. We have 
no right, he says, reverting to the arguments of the first 
Critique, to make statements about a completed universe, since 
cxperier.ee is but fragmentary. If nature provides the condi- 
tions of human life, it is no less true that man helps to provide 
the conditions of plant and animal life. Kant concludes that 
the apparent beauty and the seeming purposiveness of nature 
are no argument for religion. Religion stands or falls as a neces- 
sary presupposition of moral conduct. Because virtue evi- 
dently receives no reward on earth, Kant means, belief in God 
and immortality is required to make moral effort reasonable. 
No rational establishment of religion is possible. Religion has 
no intellectual defense, no relation to science, none to art. 

Two motives influenced Kant in this destructive third 
Critique, which suggests a rational conception of religion only 
in order to invalidate that conception. One motive was his 
desire to leave absolute authority to moral judgment, which 
he feared would be weakened by any dependence upon aes- 
thetic or even religious presuppositions. The other was his ina- 
bility' to conceive of a science not identified with mechanistic 
piijysics, or to modify in any way the assumption and conclu- 
sioms of his first Critique. TTie first and third Critiques do in 
fact collide head on, in such wise that the insight of the one 
precludes that of the other. The first Critique was concerned to 
establish universal principles supporting science; and to do this, 
Krat was compelled to deal with particular character as a mere 
fiUpng or content, wholly subjected to and articulated by these 
principles. The third Critique aimed, however, to explain the 
relation between particular character and these universal forms 
of judgment; and this required some appreciation of particular 
character as such, in itself. Kant recognized the ubiquity of 
particular character in experience, and the aesthetic faculty by 
means of which we immediately apprehend it; but he could 
not develop this empirical theme, nor allow particular character 
to mold the principles and shape the larger concepts of natural 



KANT 359 

homan thought may today be brought to a successful conclu- 
sion. But between Kant and ourselves lies a century of social 
and intellectual development which has rather radically re- 
oriented thought. We must know something of this recent 
history if we are to understand the contemporary mind. In 
reviewing this history, we should not forget that behind it 
there still stands the great issue, which we have followed since 
the beginning of our study, between those rational and em- 
pirical tendencies of mind which in their composition are 
creative thought, and in their disruption intellectual and moral 
skepticism. Kant’s problem still remains, essentially as he stated 
it in his three immortal works. One may “get around Kant,” 
as some contemporary philosophers advise — ^but only to return 
by some detour to tl^ crucial nexus of intellectual life, which 
Kant faced so squarely, and which he failed to untie only 
because of his fidelity to what seemed at that time the undeni- 
able fact that natural science stands upon a rational system of 
absolute mathematical knowledge. 


Notes for Further Reading 

1. Kant, L, The Critique of Pure Reason, trans. J. M. D. Meikle- 

john, M. Miiller, N. K Smith. New York, The Macmillan 
Gjmpany, 1914. 

2. Prolegomena to Metaphysics, ed. P. Cams. La Salle, 111 ., 

The Open Court Publishing Company, 1902. 

3. “The Critique of Practical Reason,” Theory of Ethics, 

trans. T. K Abbott. Boston, Longmans, Green and Com- 
pany, 1898. 

4. The Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard. New 

York, The Macmillan Company, 1931. Trans. J. C. Mere- 
dith. London and New York, The Oxford University Press, 
1911, 1928. 

5. The Inaugural Dissertation, etc,, trans. J. Handyside- 

La Salle, 111 ., The Open Court Publishing Company, 1929. 

6. Perpetual Peace, trans. M. C. Smith. New York, The 

Macmillan Company, 1917. 



19 DIALECTICAL IDEALISM 


Hegel, and so take up issues which are very much 
alive today, when they are the subject of controversy which 
has moved from the lecture hall to the field of battle. From 
Kant, as from Socrates in antiquity, radiated movements in 
several directions, sometimes diametrically opposed. TTie most 
important of these movements, viewed in the perspective of 
today, is that which culminated in the dialectic^ philosophies 
of Hegel and Marx. 

To understand dialectical philosophy in its historical sources, 
we must turn to a passage of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason 
entitled “transcendental dialectic.” Here Kant warns against 
the abuse of a priori principles. These principles are properly 
used empirically, i.e. in the organization by the scientist of per- 
ceptual experience or observed fact; and apart from this use, 
they are empty and describe nothing. Kant believed that when 
these organizing principles are taken to be descriptive in them- 
selves, independently of factual content, they lead to self- 
contradictions and absurdities. For example, logical principles 
are indispensable to the construction of intelligible hypotheses, 
descriptive of natural processes; but we must not suppose that 
the rules of logic constitute of themselves, prior to their ap- 

361 



dialectical idealism 363 

edge. Dialectical philosophy usually refers to the conceptual 
system elaborated by these pc«t-Kantians. 

The chief propounders of this dialectic were Fichte, Schel- 
iing, Hegel, and Marx. We will shorten our discussion by con- 
sidering only very summarily the jfirst two of these men. Fichte 
appropriated the Kantian vocabularly so thoroughly that an 
early essay was mistaken by the printer for a work of Kant, 
and published as such. The degree to which Fichte appro- 
priated the thought of Kant is at least debatable. He distin- 
guishes science which is merely empirical, and which he 
equates with materialistic philosophy, from a dialectical 
“science” which he called Wmemchaftslehre (theory of 
knowledge). The Wissenschitftslehre presents an idealistic 
metaphysics discounting the material world as only phenom- 
enal or illusory. The illusion is projected by the Self or Will 
(the “transcendental Ego”), as the condition of moral or spirit- 
ual activity. The wiU is said to project “matter” in order to 
have something to work on. When the moral will slackens, this 
phenomenal projection of the Self hardens into a material 
world, ruled by mechanical inertia and reducing those who 
believe in it to slavery. Our duty is to throw off this illusion 
of mechanical necessity, and to liberate the true Self, creative 
in moral activity. According to the manner of man you are, 
Fichte said, you will choose between a mechanical science 
Vhich enslaves you and the Wissenschaftslehre which en- 
franchises the creative Self. Fichte was also the ardent patriot 
whose Addresses to the German Nation helped to arouse Ger- 
many to resist the invader Napoleon. He assured the German 
people of their cultural unity and of their mission to spread 
this superior culture through the world. As a means to national 
unity, he advocated “the closed economic state.” Fichte’s exag- 
gerated nationalism may be excused as a reply to foreign inva- 
aon; but there is no doubt of the historical continuity between 
his teaching and the national socialism of Nazi Germany. 



dialectical idealism 


365 

Kant’s successors rejected his equivocal stand on the meta- 
physical issue. They advanced the idealistic thesis that the most 
basic principles of reason, presenting the constitution of the 
mind, must of necessity be taken to define the objective struc- 
ture of reality. This thesis is not improperly named “Objective 
Idealism,” became it claims that all the objects we know are 
mental constructs. Kant’s logical or dialectical analysis of the^ 
mind and its concepts was thus converted into a rationalistic 
metaphysics, claiming to discover by purely logical and non- 
empiiical study — ^by a sort of intellectual introspection or 
“reflection” — ^the ultimate Being which is universal reality. The 
post-Kantian dialecticians variously modify and develop Kant’s 
analysis of the categories of thought. Dialectical philosophy 
is a new, more extreme and more powerful form of the ration- 
alism which claims that final, absolute, and universal knowl- 
edge is the achievement of an intellectual intuition, going 
beyond a merely empirical science which is able to advance' 
only to probable hypothesis. Dialectical philosophy is a retuni 
to the rationalism of Plato, without his dualistic reservationsii 

To evaluate justly this powerful modem rationalism, one 
must consider the following facts. First, conceptual analysis of 
this logical sort is indispensable to every science, because 
science rightly seeks to bring into theoretical unity its diverse 
hypotheses. Only one science, physics, has as yet explicitly 
acknowledged this responsibility. The mathematical physicist 
is the “dialectician” who seeks to systematize the special hy- 
potheses advanced by experimental physicists. It is all-important 
to observe, however, that the mathematical physicist does not 
ascribe finality to his comprehensive formulations. He recog- 
nizes their tentative or hypothetical character; and he expects 
the experimental physicists to apply his theory to observable 
fact, and to confirm or disprove it by this empirical test. This 
is a proper use of logic or dialectic. It leaves logic within 
science, subject to the empirical method of science to which 
it is auxiliary. Every science might do well to follow phyacs 



DIAtECriCAL IDEAUSM 


367 

confirmed or disproved, which conditions all scientific hy- 
pothesis whatsoever. It is the postulate that real being is 
identical with individual being. This philosophical truth is to- 
day well established, as will be shown in the concluding 
chapters of this book. Dialectical philosophy substituted for 
this truth the rationalistic error: Real being is universal being. 
We shall show how this error generates the confusion of 
mind which is dialectical philosophy. But we stress here that 
the dialecticians were justified in their pursuit of a truth tran- 
scending empirical hypothesis. There is indeed the absolute and 
final truth which supports and justifies aU scientific hypothesis. 
There is scientific faith; and this needs philosophical establish- 
ment. 

And now, after having appreciated these justifiable motives 
of the dialecticians, we must be rather severely critical. Funda- 
mental to their systems is the false presumption that a reflective 
and merely conceptual analysis, unchecked by experience, can 
disclose the complete anatomy of universal nature. To reach 
their large definitions of universal structure, they simply bor- 
rowed the concepts of science current in their day, and wove 
these into a verbd pattern. They ignored or abused logic, pre- 
tending that their dialectic constituted a superlogic. The dia- 
lectic, they said, discovers necessary synthetic propositions, 
where ordinary logic discovers only analytic propositions. This 
dialectical “logic,” using its “infallible rational intuition,” is 
supposed to generate all scientific concepts in their true order, 
and to reach an absolute, all-comprehensive, and completely 
rigorous system of knowledge. This claim was really dis- 
credited by the dialecticians themselves; for their “dialectical 
logic” and “rational inmition” disclosed to different philos- 
ophers different systems, shaped to their personal predilections. 

The Hegelian system still remains the superlative example of 
dialectical construction. Hegel despised Fichte and Schelling 
for the slovenliness of their analysis; and he certainly produced 
a far more closely knit and impressive architectonic. He starts 



dialectical idealism 


369 

gradually unfolded its real but implicit content in all of the 
stages of physical and organic being; it comes to provisional 
consciousness in human intelligence; and its final and complete 
realization is philosophical understanding. Fichte identified 
ultimate reality with wUl; Schelling identified it with aesthetic 
insight; now Hegel identifies it with intellectual process. In his 
vast dialectic, Hegel tried to give meaning and plausibility to 
the idealistic thesis which states that reality is Mind, His philos- 
ophy has remained the chief resource of idealistic metaphysics. 

The contemporary thinker may also return to certain 
Hegelian insights which are broader than the dialectical sys- 
tem, and perhaps independent of it. Some would say that 
Hegel’s greatest work is not his Logic, presenting the didectic, 
but the epistemology presented in ^ Phenomenology of 
Mind, which is a sort of preface to liis more systematic writing. 
This is indeed a brilliant critique of the Kanfian philosophy, 
and possibly the most brilliant defense in any literature of 
rationalistic doctrine. 

It was necessary for any German thinker who did not iden- 
tify himself with Kant to meet and overcome the Kan tian 
critique of rationalism. We saw that Kant accepted the em- 
pirical teaching that descriptive knowledge derives wholly 
from experience, that he allowed to the pure reason only the 
task of ordering sensations entering the mind from outside, and 
that this sharp dualism of sensational material and rational 
order finally drove him to a skeptical positivism, li mi ting 
science to a knowledge of phenomena and allowing no claim 
to an intellectual grasp of “reality in itself.” In the Phenome- 
nology, Hegel criticizes Kant’s absolute separation of sensation 
and concept. The “sense-manifold” of Kant, he shows, is un- 
thinkable, and evaporates into nothing when subjected to 
scrutiny. The relation between sense-experience and knowl- 
edge is not just the relation of chaotic material to articulate 
conception. Perception itself is already perfectly articulate. 
Content void of form is as meaningless as form void of content. 



DULECnCAL roEALISM 37 1 

power of that thought or succumb to its plausibility? Let us 
insist, for the moment, that science apparently cannot subscribe 
to it! The scientist must still separate his conception, i.e. his 
theory or hypothesis, from the particular sensed material which 
suggests and confirms his thought. How else could particular 
sensed fact confirm or disprove hypothesis? The scientist, 
moreover, must esteem sensed fact even more highly than he 
esteems the most comprehensive hypothesis; for otherwise the 
observed fact could not, as it does, overtopple the great theory 
which collides with it. Our question becomes: Is there a 
rational knowledge transcending science? This question we 
shall answer aflfcnatively, but not in Hegel’s sense — ^there is no 
rational knowledge of the universe, comprehended in its 
eternal design. 

We have not yet mentioned a certain aspect of dialectical 
philosophy which is what gives to this movement its present 
hold over the public mind. The modem intellect is now passing 
through a great metamorphosis, a change so profound, and in 
its symptoms so critical, that we may wonder whether the 
crisis will be successfully endured. We may indicate the nature 
of this change by saying that it is the transition from a spatial 
to a temporal orientation upon fact. The development of 
evolutionary science, and also perhaps the physical theory of 
relativity, give some indication of this profound reorientation 
of thought; and the popular appeal of dialectical philosophy is 
due to the popular assumption, partly correct but partly mis- 
taken, that dialectical philosophy is an evolutionary doctrine, 
depicting the course of nature as it has evolved in historical 
time. We shall not be able to deal at length with this question 
here — ^that would require a separate volume; but we must stress 
the equivocal character of the dialectic, in its presentation of 
an “evolution” which at once is and is not a temporal progress. 
The dialectic requires us to conceive of an “evolution” which 
is fuUy completed, yet which eternally goes on, 

Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel all make tise of the w< j£ d ^ ^o- 



DIALECnCAL IDEALISM 


373 


of being, and suggests a serial emergence of inorganic, organic, 
and human nature. One might in fact regard dialectical 
philosophy as an impossible and disingenuous effort to alErm 
evolution implicitly, even while denying it explicitly. We are 
asked to conceive of nature “as if’ nature had evolved, even 
while denying its evolution. Reality, says the dialectician, can 
be understood only as a process of evolution; yet because the 
evolution is that of a timeless thought or reason, it is not a 
temporal nor an historical evolution. The evolution must be 
supposed eternally completed and eternally self-sustaining. 
The evolutionary process does not newly create, it only re- 
stores what eternally is. The dialectic really restates Neopla- 
tonic philosophy; and it compels us to face the question 
whether nature is in fact an eternal re-creation of this sort, or 
a temporal creation still generating new species. If Darwin was 
right, and if species originate in rime, the dialectic has no basis 
in fact. (It might be sdll defended, perhaps, on the curious sup- 
position that animals and men always existed somewhere, on 
other planets or worlds, before they emerged on earth.) 

But, in the writings of the dialecticians, this disingenuous 
“evolutionism” seems to lose its equivocal character when the 
last stages of dialectic, which ded with human society, are 
reached. In his socid didecric, Hegel drops the pretense of 
etemdism, and boldly outlines in didecricd terms the historicd 
devdopment of human government. He understands by human 
progress the long pursuit and achievement of liberty, which he 
defines as the perfect adjustment of the individud and the 
state. This part of the didecric is given separate treatment, in a 
work frankly entitled Philosophy of History-, and it was this 
socid application which interested the general public, and which 
led to large appropriation of Hegel’s thought. Hegel sketches 
at considerable length the rise of the state, in the form of an 
absolute despotism such as that of ancient China; and he follows 
its didecricd progress through Hindu anarchy, oriental empire, 
the Greek and Roman republics, Roman empire, medievd 



DIALECTICAL IDEALISM 


375 


dialectical interpretation of histoiy. We will not agree that the 
individual finds his whole self-realization in the exercise of his 
functions as a national citizen. We will not agree that the state 
has a “reality” equal or superior to that of the individual, nor 
that the state should have absolute control of education, reli- 
gion, and every cultural exercise. We vdll not accept the 
totalitarian principles, nor the state-worship, which are implicit 
in Hegel’s political theory. Nor will we accept one very large 
implication of this political interpretation of history, namely 
that human progress has been advanced exclusively or even 
rrrtcrily through war. Hegel teaches that the cosmic mecha- 
by which the succession of dominant cultures generates 
itself, is that of civic dissension and militant conquest. In spite 
of his idealistic homage to Absolute Mind or Spirit, Hegel pre- 
sents the evolution of human society in terms which make of 
it a very militaristic, material, and unspiiitual pursuit of power. 

It is unfortunate that so gifted an intellect should have been 
circumstanced and conditioned as was that of Hegel. Hegel 
looked to Prussia to unify Germany, and to support the new 
German nation against the pressure of its European neighbors. 
He became thereby, in spite of his liberal inclinations, the chief 
intellectual spokesman of the reactionary movement which 
followed the debacle of the French revolution. The totalitarian 
“theory of the state,” by which Hegel intended to make the 
unity and security of Germany the controlling objective of 
every German and the ruling principle of German life, did in 
fact guide Germany through several aggressive wars and to 
enormous power; but the final issue of this teaching is political 
collapse and moral rum. Unfortunately, the extreme national- 
ism which engenders, and which is again fostered by, this 
“theory of the state” has spread to every people. The imme- 
diate intention of the Hegelian political realism is to support 
unjust privilege, by attributing to those actually in political 
control, the de facto government, a mystical identity w ith the 
“spirit” of the people and a sanctified power. 



MALECnCAI, TOEAUSM 377 

3. The Science of Ethics, trans. A. E Kroeger. London, 

K. Paul, Trench, Truber and Ojmpany, 1897. 

There are studies of Fichte in English by Adamson, Everett, 
Thompson, Talbot, Royce (in The Spirit of Modem Philos- 
ophy, Boston, Houghton Mifflin Company, 1899), 
Pringle-Pattison (in From Krnit to Hegel, listed below). 

4. Mead, G. H., Movements of Thought in the Nineteenth Cen- 

tury. Chicago, Chicago University Press, 1936. 

5. Pringle-Pattison, A. S., from Kant to Hegel. New York, G. E. 

Steckert and Company, 1924. 

6. Hegel, G. W. F., Phenomenology of Mind, trans. J. B. Baillie. 

New York, The Macmillan Company, 1931. 

7. Science of Logfc, trans. W. H. Johnston and L- G. 

Struthers. New York, The Macmillan Company, 1929. 

8. Logic of World and Idea, trans. Macran. London and 

New York, Oxford University Press, 1929. 

9. “Logic and Philosophy of Mind,” trans. W. Wallace, 

Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences. London and 
New York, Oxford University Press, 1892, 

10. Introduction to the Philosophy of Fine Art, trans. B. 

Bosanquet. New York, Harcourt, Brace and Company, 192 1. 

11. Philosophy of History, trans. J, Sibree. New York, 

Colonial Press, 1902. 

12. Loewenberg, J., Hegel: Selections. New York, Charles Scrib- 

ner’s Sons, 1929. 

13. Mure, G. R. C., An Introduction to Hegel. London and New 

York, Oxford University Press, 1940. 

14. Stace, W. Y., The Philosophy of Hegel. New York, The Mac- 

millan Company, 1924. 

15. Croce, B., What is Living and Dead in the Philosophy of 

Hegel, trans. D. Ainslee. London, The Macmillan Company, 
1915. 

There are also studies in English of the Hegelian metaphysics 
and epistemology by J. M. E. McTaggart and H. A. 
Pritchard. 

1 6. Hobhouse, L. T., The Mztsph'jslcd Theory of the State. New 

York, The Macmillan Company, 1918. 

17. Foster, M. B., The Political Philosophies of Plato and Hegel. 

London and New York, Oxford University Press, 1935. 



20 


DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM 


It is perhaps a good sign, indicating a grovptng 
realism, that the contemporary mind entertains in 
dialectical philosophy a faith which, although it proceeds from 
rationalistic premises, nevertheless submits itself in the end to 
the test of empirical fact. The dialectic claims to show a neces- 
sary sequence in social history, a fatalistic direction discern- 
ible in past history and dominating of necessity the movement 
from present to future. This is to give to philosophy the role 
of prophecy, and to make the power to predict our final cri- 
terion of truth. One cannot consider dialectical philosophies 
purely academically, without reference to the social history 
which they claim to describe and foresee. This is the way 
society did, does, and must go, says the dialectician; and we 
are challenged to look and see whether it is in actual fact the 
way society goes. 

The Hegelian dialectic took the national state to be ti e 
oi^an of social progress. For the impetus of progress, it looked 
idealistically to the intelligence of a people, effective in its in- 
tellectual elite. When we speak of history, we usually mean 
political history; and Hegel only conformed to orthodox opin- 
ion when he made the state the agency of social progress, this 
being the implicit assumption of most historians prior to Hegel 


379 



DIAtECTICAL MATERIALISM 


381 

forces themselves. If economic fact determines political fact, 
we can determine what in our society shall be economic fact. 
We can regulate the national economy by means of political 
action; and this is to invert the Marxist view, and to revert to 
the Hegelian position. And now we perceive that political 
leadership w'as never so unaware of the Marxist truth that it 
omitted to secure some large control of the national economy. 
Throughout all history, governments have existed primarily 
for this purpose. Do not Marxists agree that any government 
which fails to do this is on the way outi^ The simple truth 
is that “the nation” is a political-economic system. The science 
of government is neither political history nor economic science, 
but political economy. What the Marxist correctly perceives 
is that the economic organization of society has increasingly 
overborne national boundaries, until it is no longer subject to 
political control. There grew up a new and large economy 
which today is world-wide. Our present convulsions are the 
effort to bring this larger economy under political control. 
Economic change gives rise to new political problems; but the 
solution of these problems is the creation of political institutions 
bringing economic change under new control. Economic activ- 
ities condition political activities; and the result of political 
activity is to recondition economy. 

We need, accordingly, a new social science, one that can 
appropriate both of the two half-truths which respectively 
support the Hegelian and Marxist dialectics. This science must, 
of course, undercut the error which is the dialectical method 
itself. Dialectical philosophy violates the first principle of 
science, which is the requirement of carnal explanation. The 
dialectic, we said, arises out of the confusion of causal connec- 
tion with logical implication. This is really a confusion of fact 
with language — ^the very confusion which the nominalistic 
founders of empirical science hoped to eradicate. 

Our initial purpose here must be to do intellectual and moral 
justice to the Marxist philosophy of dialectical materialism. We 



DIAUECnCAL MATERIALISM 


383 

ligatory upon the social scientist. Very much as Darwin trans- 
formed all biological science by establishing it upon an evolu- 
tionary basis, very much as Newton established physical science 
upon universal laws of motion, so Marx inaugurated an em- 
pirical social science when he multiplied evidence of the casual 
connections relating social institutions to the social economy 
which conditions them. 

There is some controversy today as to whether Marx him- 
self was an “economic determinist” of the radical sort, who 
sees in all political and ideological fact only the manifestation 
of economic process. Neither party to the controversy has 
difEcnlty in finding passages in the writings of Marx to sup- 
port its view. Neither party is mistaken, because Marx the 
social scientist was not an “economic determinist,” whereas 
Marx the dialectical philosopher of necessity was this. Marx 
frequently and emphatically states the intelligible and true 
thesis that economic conditions constitute the most ubiquitous, 
constant, and dominant factor in social history, carnally nijork- 
ing upon the other political and ideological factors. Writing 
as a social scientist, Marx takes causation seriously and offers 
a truly scientific h)q>othesis. The economic factor could not 
be a causal factor, it would have nothing to work upon, if 
there did not exist in society other relatively independent fac- 
tors in political and other institutions. But when Marx is writ- 
ing as a dialectician he foregoes causal explanation in order to 
indulge in dialectical or “logical” explanation; and now the 
economic pattern becomes not merely the essential and domi- 
nant factor which it in fact is, but the constitutive and sub- 
stantial Being of society, manifesting itself indifferently in 
economic, political, ideological and other forms. Here we 
relinquish the causal analysis of science, in order to pursue 
rationalistic metaphysics with its pseudological explanations. 

If we reflect upon this contrast of Marx the scientist with 
Alarx the rationalist, we shall discover the radical confusion 
of mind which generated dialectical philcsorhy, and which 



DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM 385 

authoritative social theory comparable with physical theory. 
It is because of this paucity of established social theory that we 
have recourse to social history; for we correctly conclude that 
the course of history provided by the responsible historian 
indicates causal processes which the theorist has not yet 
elucidated and defined. Social scientists are at present divided 
into two groups, one of sociologists devoted to social theory, 
and one of historians seeking to enlarge history. What we need 
today is greater cooperation between social theorists and social 
historians. This cooperation will scarcely be smooth and fruit- 
ful without clear understanding of the relationship between 
social theory and social history. Should sociology swallow up 
historical science, the historian becoming a collector of hi^ 
torical data useful to the social theorist? Or is history an in- 
dependent study, proceeding without the help of theoretical 
guidance, and providing real knowledge of social process in 
spite of its nontheoretical character? 

The distinction between social history and social theory lies 
in their respective uses of causal explanation. Both provide 
causal explanation; but the theorist explains the causal sequence 
of events as the manifestation of some known general principle, 
whereas the historian discovers causal connections to exist 
among particular events, whether or not the causal sequence 
illustrates some general principle. We meet here once again 
the ancient question which divides the rationalist and the 
empiricist: Do general laws actually cause particular events to 
emerge as they do? Or is all causation particular causation, the 
so-called “laws” being only our summaries of many observed 
particular causations? Be it observed that there is no quarrel 
between the theorist and the historian on this point. Both agree, 
as all ^ientists today agree, that “causation” means particular 
causation, and that generalization only discovers shnilarities 
among particul^ causal sequences. There is no “law” which 
necessitates particulars to be what they are and to act as they 
do. But the theorist is interested in particular events insofar as 



DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM 


387 

torical hypothesis advanced by Marx, describing how the 
economic processes of medieval and modem society did in fact 
help to determine political and other history. We may dis- 
tinguish Marx the scientist from Marx the dialectician, and 
judge his tremendous historical hypothesis impartially, taking 
it out of rationalistic polemics into empirical science, where it 
can be confirmed or disproved by factual evidence. 

Marx took his communistic principles from post-Napoleonic 
France. His reading of European history was influenced by his 
long sojourn in industrialized England. But he was still condi- 
tioned in his thought by his earlier life in Germany, and as 
his thought matured, it took a form directly antithetical, and 
therefore in its largest character similar, to that of Hegel. 
Marx, it must never be forgotten, w'as a Hegelian. Hegel had 
conceived history to be a drama centered in the political evolu- 
tion of government; and Marx never really rejects this political 
orientation. But Hegel had conceived only of a national state 
controlled by a prmleged intellectual elite and advancing by 
way of national expansion; and this political orthodoxy had 
made him the spokesman of world-wide reaction against the 
universalistic principles of republicanism. Marx challenged this 
intellectual Goliath; and to defeat Hegel on his own ground 
he accepted HegeFs dialectical premises and also his political 
orientation, diverging in order to place the ultimate controls of 
political history in the people instead of in a privileged elite. 
This was the primary aim, we may perhaps agree, of the Marxist 
doctrine. Marx wished to show that it is the actual labor of 
the worker in the field or the shop, something he called the 
“mode of production,” that finally dominates all economic, 
pclitical. and intellectual life. 

The rationalist, like the Aristotelian philosopher, must radi- 
cally distinguish the essential form of a thing from the non- 
essential matter which it informs. The essential form of a thing 
is ultimately the universe working in that thing, and con- 
trolling its development and destiny. For Hegel, the essence 



DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM 389 

an increase of population, and that this is good. We must still 
observe that the mode of production, although it may condi- 
tion every social institution, is only one of many factors. 
Ciarist Russia with its serfdom, early New England with its 
freehold farms, and the colonial South with its slave plantations 
were all agricultural societies; yet how different their political 
patterns! Twentieth-century Russia, Germany, and the United 
States are all industrialized; yet how different their govern- 
ments! Marx confused the fact that economic activities condi- 
tion political activities with the supposition that economic form 
(the dominant mode of production) detennines political form 
(the constitution of a society). This supposition cannot be 
defended. Liberty and tyranny are both possible in every so- 
ciety, whatever its economic mode of production. Economic 
progress does not necessarily entail political progress. 

Marx was misled by the old fallacy of a necessary human 
progress. This fallacy is a rationalistic misstatement of the 
truth that there has in fact been much human progress, both 
economic and political. Economic progress is increased eco- 
nomic efficiency, which may be measured by the weight of 
product produced by one hour of human labor. This mightily 
increases as we move from agricultural to industrial society. 
There has been great economic progress. Political progress 
should be measured by the degree to which each and every 
individual participates in government, thus securing due con- 
trol both of his individual economy and of the political econ- 
omy. There has also been politicd progress. But there is no 
necessary relation between economic progress and political 
progress, nor is there any necessary progress of any sort. 
Russia by political means advances the economic progress of 
its vast domain, Germany by political means would have kept 
much of Europe agricultural. It is very clear to the discerning 
historian that the history of modem civilization is primarily 
the story of how economic and political progress have stimu- 
lated each other, and how failures of political progress have 



DULECriCAL MATERIALISM 


391 

which tries to see in physical necesity itself a god in disguise, 
taking Protean shape in biological, psychological, sociological, 
or other necessity. But in the twentieth century, when modem 
science has long been freed from its rationalistic swaddling 
clothes, and when every scientist and every intelligent and in- 
formed person knows that physical and other scientific “laws” 
are not universal natural necessities, but only our latest sum- 
maries of observed similarities, this residue of medieval ration- 
alism has no place. We cannot change the physical habits of 
astronomical nature, and so we must accept its “laws”; but we 
certainly can change, and every day do change, the social 
habits of men and women. We do this by means of legislation, 
education, example, and persuasion. Society knows no law 
which it does not make itself, except that utter moral law 
which is the rule of all that exists, and which we have yet to 
elucidate. 

We have considered dialectical materialism only in its social 
application, and have not referred to its larger doctrine, pro- 
fessedly showing how material being by dialectical necessity 
proceeds to unfold its implicit content of physical, organic, 
and, finally, social pattern. Nor shall we summarize this larger 
doctrine, if only because it can scarcely be said to exist, neither 
Marx nor any authoritative Marxist having troubled to elab- 
orate it. Its materialism is a vague verbal gesture, dismissing 
idealism. The gesture is necessarily vague, because the concept 
of dialectical necessity is incorrigibly idealistic in its confusion 
of causal connection with logic^ explanation. Marx seems to 
have thought that his emphasis on material production re- 
quired a materialistic metaphysics — as if the production of ma- 
terial goods by human labor were somehow only a physical 
process, and not as biological, psychological, and moral a 
process as writing poetry, devising political systems, or elab- 
orating rationalistic metaphysics. But further, the discussion of 
contemporary materialism, including that of Marxists, would 



dialectical materialism 


393 


Notes for Further Reading 

1. Marx, K., Capital^ trans. Aveling. New York, Charles Scribner’s 

Sons, 1925. 

2. Capitaly etc.y ed. M, Eastman. New York, Modern 

Library, Inc., 1932. 

The Essentials of Marx, ed. A. Lee. New York, Rand 

Book Store, 1931. 

A Handbook of Marxismy ed. E. Bums. New York, 

International Publishers Company, Inc., 1935. 

5. Engels, F., Lud'wig Feuerbach and the Outcome of German 

Classical Philosophy y ed. C. P. Dutt. Moscow, Cooperative 
Publishing Society, and New York, International Publishers 
Company, Inc., 1934. 

6. Lenin, N., Materialis?n and Empirico-Criticismy trans. D. Kvitko 

and S. Hook. Moscow, Cooperative Publishing Society, and 
New York, International Publishers Company, Inc., 1927. 

7. Lewns, J., ed. A Textbook of Marxist Philosophy. Moscow, 

The Leningrad Institute of Philosophy, 1938. 

8. Plekhanov, G. V., Fundamental Problem of Marxismy ed. D. 

Ryazanov, trans. E. and C. Paul. London, M. Lawrence, 
Ltd., 1929. 

9. Bukharin, N. L, Historical Materialism. New York, Interna- 

tional Publishers Company, Inc., 1925. 

and others, Marxism and Modem Thoughty trans. R. 

Fox, New York, Harcourt, Brace and Company, 1935. 

1 1. Bernstein, E., Evolutionary Socialismy trans. E. C. Harvey, New 

York, B. W. Huebsch, 1909. 

12. Seligman, E. R. A., The Economic Interpretation of History. 

New York, Columbia University Press, 1924. 

13. Lindsay, A. D., Karl Marx*s Capital London and New York, 

Oxford University Press, 1931. 

14. Laski, H. J., Karl Marx. New York, League for Industrial 

Democracy, 1933. 

15. Hook, S., From Hegel to Marx. New York, Reynal and Hitch- 

cock, Inc., 1936. 

16. Cole, G. D. H., What Marx Really Meant. New York, Alfred 

A. Knopf, 1934. 

17. Haldane, J. B. S., The Marxist Philosophy and the Sciences. 

New York, Random House, Inc., 1939. 



21 


THE NINETEENTH CENTURY 


^^VER MUCH OF THE EARTH’s SURFACE, THE 

nineteenth century was a period of economic, politi- 
cal, and scientific progress such as the world had never seen. 
In Europe and the continents settled by its emigrants there 
was vast increase of population and of wealth. The indigenous 
populations of Asia and Africa were in effect subjugated by 
Europe, and not yet inclined to revolt. It was a century of 
relative peace, a long lull between the world war against 
Napoleon and that in which Germany would seek world 
empire. Politically, it was the century of imperialism. Britain 
was able to police the seas at little cost; and its power was 
tolerated because its policy of free trade made its hegemony 
profitable to all. The Americas and Russia were busy with 
internal expansion, France had moderated its imperialistic ambi- 
tions, Germany was not yet ready for its great gamble; and 
so peace was had by default. 

We see today that it was an interim period, a last calm be- 
fore the storm which in terrible convulsion would end that 
imperialistic age, and begin a new world no longer centered 
in Europe, But the nineteenth century dreamed of no such 
cataclysm. It looked forward to an indefinite future, in which 
its pattern of life would spread to the world at large. It sup- 


395 



THE NINETEENTH CENTURY 397 

cally, as a pursuit of or special interests. The aim of 

the state must be, he said, to satisfy private interests by their 
union in public interests, and to educate its citizens by per- 
suading them of this identity between private and public in- 
terests. The character of the individual, he taught, is determined 
wholly by the social environment; and moral character should 
be shaped by the state, which is thus the source of individual 
morality. The best state is that which seeks “the greatest good 
of the greatest number.” 

This conception is almost irrelevant to democratic theory. It 
defines aims which might be those of any government; but it 
says nothing about the sources and controls of governmental 
power- Democratic theory is distinguished from all other po- 
litical theory by its location of responsibility in the moral in- 
dividual, i.e. in all individuals. It is a political and moral faith, 
not a psychological theory nor an ethical doctrine. Democratic 
society may seek to realize through its appointed government 
any specific moral end; and its objectives will vary at different 
times and places. The utilitarian conception becomes definitely 
antidemocratic when it is conjoined with the view that the 
state is the source of individual morality. Jeremy Bentham in- 
troduced Helvetius’ formula into British thought, in a utilitarian 
program which demanded for government an unlimited legal 
sovereignty; and he roundly repudiated the principle of natural 
ri^ts. The sole test of law, Bentham argued, is its utility in 
securing the general welfare. This Benthamite movement 
helped to bring about the extension of democratic suffrage; 
but it did this as a means necesary to the passage of legal and 
other reforms, and not as an acknowledgment of democratic 
principles. Following the year 1832, when conservative reac- 
tion broke down, this reform group gave to Great Britain a 
century of progressive and liberal leadership; but democratic 
thought never fully recovered its grasp of the principle of 
individual responsibility, upon which alone democracy can be 
intelligibly and firmly established. Thus a century which tre- 



■niE NINETEENTH CENTURY 


399 

the high optunism it had inherited steadily thinned and vul- 
garized itself, losing its impetus, until the confused impulse to 
faith was ashamed of faith, and retracted to a more honest 
skepticism. Schopenhauer, who saw the beginning of this cen- 
tury, was prescient of its end. 

Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860) was a contemporary of 
Schelling and Hegel; and his greatest work, The World as Will 
and as Idea, was written in i8i8 when he was thirty years old. 
Yet in his thought Schopenhauer was closer to ourselves than 
to his German contemporaries. Like those men, he moved from 
the great Kantian criticism to a form of metaphysical idealism; 
but his sojourns in France and England, together with his 
wide reading, had made of him a cosmopolitan thinker whose 
writings can be intelligibly rendered into any language. At 
first ignored, Schopenhauer before his death received wide 
recognition, and became something of a popular idol. His 
direct influence was upon the general public rather than upon 
professional philosophers; and this has perhaps obscured from 
us how great his influence was. 

His first contribution was a simplification of the Kantian 
philosophy; but this simplification rather profoundly modified 
Kant’s system. Kant had called space and time the two forms 
of perception; and he had made causation a category of the 
understanding. Schopenhauer taught that the two concepts of 
^ace and time of themselves compose the concept of physical 
causation, a view which finds some support in contemporary 
physical theory. He concluded that the spatial-temporal-causal 
pattern of fact is generated in perception alone, without help 
from the understanding. What then is the imderstanding and 
the scientific knowledge which it produces.^" The understand- 
ing, Schopenhauer says, seeks an abstract summary or general- 
ization of causal relationships immediately perceived. Percep- 
tion alone provides factual truth; but the understanding pro- 
vides, in science, a useful schedule or compendium of perceived 
fact. With the help of this schedule, we can predict and con- 



the nineteenth century 


401 

resistances, with other wills. All nature is this endless battle- 
field of conflicting wills. What we perceive is what threatens or 
supports our will-to-live. What is irrelevant to our personal 
survival we do not perceive. So, after first contrasting the 
falsity of systematic science with the truth of perception, 
Schopenhauer now tells us that perception also is a pragmatic 
and utilitarian faculty, and not an authentic, objective cogni- 
tion; for our perception is the “objectification” only of our 
subjective purpose, our personal will-to-live; and it reveals, con- 
sequently, only a private perspective, in terms of our will or 
our vital needs. Perceptual cognition is true but subjective. 

This conception is close to that elaborated by Bergson early 
in this century. Bergson makes science and ordinary perception 
the projection into nature of our practical and vital needs. In 
both thinkers there is this curious self-contradiction, that they 
at once dismiss science as an instrument not intended to provide 
descriptive knowledge, yet unconsciously appeal to science for 
the evidence for their conclusion. Does not science, Schopen- 
hauer argues, demonstrate nature to be a conflict of interacting 
forces? Is not this concept of force the ground principle of 
modem science? What are forces but wills, and what are 
wills but forces seeking self-furtherance? But immediately, 
forgetting this involuntary and illogical appeal to science as a 
descriptive and trae portrait of nature, Schopenhauer returns 
to his doctrine that natural science and theoretical philosophy 
only depict our personal perspective upon nature, which is de- 
termined by our private character and needs. 

Thus the will, after all, although it is noumenal or real, pro- 
vides no knowledge but only useful illusion — ^useful to the 
amoral, wholly egoistic will-to-live, which seeks its own fur- 
therance against all other wills. This skeptical conclusion ex- 
presses the profound pessimism which is rightly attributed to 
Schopenhauer and which was widely inculcated by his writ- 
ings. But Schopenhauer himself seeks to transcend this skepti- 
cism and pessimism. We have, he says, a third faculty, one 



THE NINETEENTH CENTURY 


403 

tradictions spring from vacillation with respect to natural 
science. Science is sometimes abruptly rejected as error, some- 
times used to establish Schopenhauer’s own doctrine. These 
inconsistencies might be overcome, perhaps, if we allowed 
biological science, rather than physical theory, to represent 
natu^ science. Schopenhauer, like Kant, identifies natural 
science with physical science; but his emphasis upon the will- 
to-survive, upon specific form, and upon the individual’s self- 
sacrifice to the needs of its species suggests the initial step 
toward a new approach to natural process. The complete re- 
moval of Schopenhauer’s contradictions, however, would be 
effected only by a study explaining the essential and funda- 
mental role of aesthetic apprehension in all science, physics as 
well as biology — ^it would require, that is to say, the successful 
rewriting of Kant’s third Critique. 

Schopenhauer’s writings helped to propagate the voluntar- 
ism, the anti-mtellectual pragmatism, and the vague aestheticism 
which ran under the surface of nineteenth-century thought, to 
erupt in explicit end extreme forms in our own century. Like 
Fichte, Hegel, and Marx, Schopenhauer helped to widen a 
growing disruption in the modem mind. Fichte set philosophy 
against science; Hegel set people against people; Marx set 
class against class; and Schopenhauer now sets art against 
science, and the will-to-live against the disinterested intellect. 
What was the source of this unhappy division of the human 
mind against itself.^ A fatal malcontent inspires these philoso- 
phies. In the cases of Fichte and Hegel, this malaise comes to 
light only in the destructive political results of their teaching; 
but in ^hopenhauer, it is conscious and explicit. From this 
world, with its unholy straggle for survival and power, he 
intimates, we find release only in complete abnegation of the 
will-to-live, t.e. in death. Even more strange, from the pen of 
this worldly cosmopolitan aesthete, is the intimation that salva- 
tion lies in the sacrifice of the individual for his kind, which is 
a sort of atonement for the sin that is the world. The other- 



the nineteenth century 405 

From this subjectivistic fantasy he advanced to a legai^liC or 
metaphysical stage, in which absolute principles or “laws” 
were supposed to rule over nature. Today, at last, men recog- 
nize the subjectivism of these philosophies which seek vainly 
to penetrate through appearances to “reality.” Men now accept 
sensible appearances, or phenomena, as the sum of knowledge, 
and seek only to classify the regular sequences observable 
among phenomena. Awareness of such uniformities permits 
calculated prediction, giving to man some control over natural 
occurrence; and with ultimate knowledge he may now dis- 
pense. This is Comte’s ■posithnsm. 

In truth, this modest and empirical estimate of human knowl- 
edge is largely window dressing, intended to attract the scien- 
tific mind and to make formal renunciation of the older and 
now discredited scholastic metaphysics. Comte’s positivism is 
really supported by unconscious metaphysical assumptions. 
This metaphysical framework makes its appearance as a classi- 
fication of the sciences. The sciences naturally fall, Comte 
points out, into a definite sequence, proceeding from the mathe- 
matical sciences, through the physical and biological sciences, 
to the sciences which deal with man and society. The sciences 
antecedent in this order are presupposed in and instrumental to 
those which follow; and the sciences accordingly culminate 
in sociology, which telescopes into its theory all the principles 
of the other sciences. Because of this relationship, the sciences 
become more complex and difficult as we proceed in this order, 
from mathematics to sociology; and this is why they were 
historically developed in this order. Comte regarded himself 
as the originator of empirical sociology. He may have invented 
the name; but his social analyds is less empirical and scientific 
than that of many of his predecessors. 

As we have seen, this “order of the sciences” reflects primarily 
the fact of natural evolution on this planet. Comte was no 
evolutionist. For him, consequently, the order of the sciences 
constituted an ultimate metaphysical fact, not to be empirically 



the nineteenth centhry 


407 

“social statics” and “social d3mamics.” In physical science 
this division into statics and dynamics has meaning. Physical 
statics deals with stresses in bodies at rest, whereas physical 
dynamics is the study of bodies in motion; and the two 
disciplines apply the same basic principles to two sorts of 
physical situation. This distinction cannot be simply translated 
to sociology. What Comte calls “social statics” is a study 
modeled on physical dynamics. It seeks a social theory defining 
the constants always and everywhere conserved through social 
change. What he calls “social dynamics” is really an historical 
study of human progress, in no way analogous to phyacal 
dynamics. This error is worth noting, because it makes unusu- 
ally explicit the long confusion which has obscured our con- 
ceptions of social and natural evolution. Comte correctly dis- 
tinguishes the historical study of human progress from the 
theoretical study which defines the social structure which is 
supposedly preserved throughout this evolution; but he in- 
correctly conceives of these two studies, respectively historical 
and theoretical, as the two halves of a single theoretical science 
analogous with theoretical physics. This is only another version 
of the error committed by Hegel in his dialectic. The dialectic 
“progresses” from a beginning to an end, like a history or an 
evolution; yet it claims to be a theoretical system, defining the 
unchanging and absolute structure of the world. We will return 
to this problem in our study of evolutionary doctrine. 

We have already mentioned Gimte’s outline of man’s in- 
tellectual evolution as proceeding through three st^es, from 
animistic mythology through metaphysical speculation to 
positivistic science. His elaboration of this doctrine is sugges- 
tive; it is, in fact, the prototype of the social dialectic of Marx. 
Each stage, Cbmte says, produces its characteristic social insti- 
nitions. The earliest theological stage is marked by the develop- 
ment of ecclesiastical and military institutions; the metaph 5 rsical 
stage is characterized by the establishment of constitutional 
governments and of legalistic forms of social control. We sdU 



the nineteenth century 409 

Herbert Spencer (1820-1903) exhibits this same failure. 
Spencer was long regarded in English-speaking countries as 
the chief philosophical exponent of evolutionary doctrine. In 
truth he belongs to the early nineteenth century, with Hegel 
and Comte, in his explanation of evolutionary facts in terms of 
nonevolutionary principles. His extensive system, elaborated 
in a small library of volumes the writing of which occupied his 
long life, reveals his dogmatic and unempirical method, which 
resembles that of Hegel in its mechanical imposition of a verbal 
formula upon the diverse materials provided by the special 
sciences. He is like Comte, however, in his ostensible repudia- 
tion of metaphysics. He prefaces his system with a call to 
agnosticism, warning us not to pursue knowledge of the 
“Absolute,” which is beyond human comprehension. We are 
limited to knowledge of phenomena and their uniformities. 
But having thus eliminated the word “absolute,” Spencer turns 
to the construction of a universalistic metaphysics which is 
absolutisdc in all but name, and which closely parallels the 
dialectical metaphysics. There are, he says, a number of a priori 
and absolute principles involved in our recognition of “phe- 
nomena”; and the most important of these is the principle of 
necessary development, according to which matter proceeds 
to its spatial reorganization by an inherent necessity, from the 
most simple physical patterns to increasingly complex in- 
organic, organic, and psychological patterns. The sciences, ar- 
ranged in their proper order, exhibit the successive stages of 
this material development of nature; and all Spencer need do, 
or does, is to present the many concepts of inorganic, organic, 
and human science as arising from this “necessity,” under 
which “matter” labors, progressively to complicate its spatial 
pattern. It need scarcely be pointed out that this Spencerian 
“matter” corresponds in no way to what modern science has 
understood by this word. The reader will perceive Spencer’s 
revival here of the Aristotelian and scholastic concept of matter, 
which was defined as the potentiality to realize form; but the 



the nineteenth centory 41 r 

application of a more general ethical theory; and in his ethical 
writings, Mill remained vacillating and inconclusive. He was 
not satisfied with the utilitarianism of his father and Bentham; 
yet he seriously considered no alternative, and his effort to 
modify its hedonistic axioms only left them meaningless and 
inapplicable. Pleasure is the objective of every human act, he 
hedonistically agreed, and the good is therefore to be defined 
by a hedonistic calculus, correctly calculating the maximum 
jaim of accessible pleasures. He insisted, however, that pleasures 
must be estimated qualitatively, as well as quantitatively. Mill, 
and after him other hedonists, never clearly perceived that a 
rational calculation of pleasures — and still more, of course, a 
qualitative estimate of pleasures as higher or lower — appeals 
to ethical criteria lying beyond the immediate feeling of pleas- 
ure. Assuming that pleasure is the object of an instinctive and 
rightful urge, how shall man direct and control this instinctive 
pursuit of pleasure, to gain from it its optimum outcome? 
Even to ask this question involves the postulation of some 
intellectual ethical criterion over and above that of pleas- 
urableness. 

A similar vacillation appears in his political writings. Mill 
supported the consequences which flow from the principle of 
i nalienab le rights; yet he feared what might result from the 
full application of this principle. His defense of minorities, for 
example, was motivated by his fear that an electoral majority 
might oppress minorities. Such half-hearted allegiance to demo- 
cratic principles did not strengthen liberalism. British liberalism 
was largely a creation of the antimonarchical but still aristo- 
cratic WWg party, which supported an extension of political 
suffrage to gain popular support against the Tory opposition. 
A genuine liberalism (and we should not let the inadequacies 
of earlier liberals rob us of this word) is established upon 
faith in the individual man, and is incompatible with fear of 
“the masses” and with the very concept of “the masses.” 
Liberalism is our faith that the inividual human being is good. 



the nineteenth century 


413 

the scientific analysis which is auxiliary to hypothesis. The 
true method of science is the creation of hypotheses; and this 
eludes definition. 

Our justification for applying a generalization from past 
facts to facts as yet unobserved. Mill says, rests upon the largest 
generalization, which is derived from the sum total of past 
generalizations. Having made many successful inductions in 
special fields, we now make a general induction, stating that 
nature is evidently amenable to inductive study. This largest 
generalization Mill calls “the principle of the uniformity of 
nature.” It was immediately pointed out that this reasoning is 
circular. The specific inductions are “successful” only if we 
grant their necessary applicability to unobserved fact, and this 
is what needs proof. What proof is there that nature is uniform? 

Mill’s teaching may be summarized as follows; Our only 
problem, he assumes, is to distinguish genuinely causal se- 
quences from merely casual or chance repetitions. The method 
of agreement compares an observed sequence with earlier 
observed sequences. The method of difference instructs us, if 
abc has always been followed by def, to see whether the ab- 
sence of f in the consequent does not entail the absence of ^ in 
the antecedent, in which case c is presumably the cause of f. 
The method of residues says that if abc is the uniform ante- 
cedent of def, and ah the uniform antecedent of de, then, once 
more, c is the cause of f. And the method of concormtcmt 
variations tells us that where one factor varies quantitatively 
with another, the two factors are probably causally connected. 
The occasional admiration of a scientist for these trivial defini- 
tions of “scientific method” reminds one of the surprise and 
pleasure of Monsieur Jourdain, when he was assured by his 
tutor that he was able to speak in prose, and indeed always did 
so speak. If this is scientific method, then who is not a Newton? 
“Inductive logic” has cheapened our estimate of science; and 
those who would have science receive the intelligent respect 
which is its due should protest this abuse in no uncertain terms. 



the kineteenth centoty 


415 

Aristotelian metaphysics, as this was perpetuated in the scholas- 
tic theology and philosophy. These modem thinkers believed 
themselves to be rejecting all metaphysical speculation when 
they emphatically rejected the scholastic metaphysics; yet they 
unconsciously introduced new metaphysics of their own. Their 
own metaphysics they disguised as a “method.” They were 
unaware that every method, if it is advanced as universal in its 
applicability and authoritative in its results, implies certain 
absolute assumptions which provide the generative nucleus 
of a body of metaphysical doctrine. Descartes and Spinoza, 
who initiated the most extreme rationalism the western world 
has seen, conceived themselves to be free from metaph)7sical 
assumptions and to be advocating only a “method.” But simi- 
larly the nominalists and empiricists, who rejected the Cartesian 
along with the scholastic metaphysics, were the proponents of 
a metaphysical view, resting upon absolute axioms, but dis- 
guised as only scientific method. Normnalisnt asserts the abso- 
lute and tdtinme reality of individual being, as observed in 
particular things and occurrences; and this is a metaphysicd 
affirmation. Empiricism likevnse, although it allovos only prob- 
ability to its general statements, makes observed particular fact 
the ultimate and sufficient criterion of truth; and this is to 
subscribe to the nommdistic axiom. But it has never been per- 
ceived voith sufficient clarity that the empirical realism •which 
is modem science, like the rationalistic realism vohich oBas 
Greek science, constitutes a metaphysics. We need not vjonder 
at the gyc-wing confusion of empirical thinkers •who •were not 
arware of their o'wn first principles, presupposed in all their 
method. 

As empirical thought bogged down into confusion and 
triviality, there inevitably appeared a reaction against it, and a 
new appreciation of the clarity and forthrightness of ration- 
alistic thinkers who openly confessed to their metaphysical 
postulates. We caimot follow nineteenth-century thought 
through aU of its many movements; but we may note its 



the nineteenth century 


417 

knowledge of universal natural principles, is not invalidated 
by criticism of his atomistic psychology. But Green assumed 
that his discovery of flaws unessential to Hume’s central argu- 
ment invalidated Hume’s whole conclusion; and he returns 
with a leap to an absolute, universalistic, and idealistic meta- 
physics. Because the elements of experience are not isolated 
atoms, he concludes that a perfected experience contains no 
separations, no fragmentary character, no elements of any sort. 
The whole of experience, he claims, is somehow inherent in 
every part of experience. The whole mind, with its whole 
knowledge, informs our every judgment. Yet having so argued. 
Green must retreat in order to acknowledge the limitations of 
human knowledge, the lapses of mind, the lacunae and errors 
of human experience. It is not your or my imperfect mind, 
he allows, which has this perfect organization and this trans- 
parent wholeness and unity. But such is Absolute Mind, of 
which our minds are imperfect and fragmentary parts, and of 
which all fact is the infinite and unified content. Similarly, 
our particular actions and our individual wills are the real 
modes of a universal, eternal, and absolute Will. Reality is an 
organized Whole; and in organized human society we intend, 
so far as our limited and modal natture allows, a proper sub- 
jection of our individual will to the absolute Will which is God. 

The two most notable British exponents of absolute idealism 
were Bradley and Bosanquet. Francis H. Bradley (1846-1924) 
was the profounder of the two. Because he probed deep, he 
brought again to the surface of thought the insoluble problems 
which Kant had acknowledged and clearly marked, but which 
Kant’s absolutisdc successors had overridden. Bradley resur- 
rects, and remains inextricably caught in, those antinomies or 
self-contradictions which Kant had shown to be latent in ab- 
solute and universal metaphysics. How, Bradley inquires, 
can the limited human mind, analyzing a finite experience, hope 
to establish principles of universal and eternal validity? If 
Reality, as absolute idealism implies, is an organic Whole, to 



the nineteenth century 419 

now a whale.” If we err, and say, “The whale is a fish,” when 
better acquaintance would classify it as a mammal, our error is 
one of extent, not of intent. Wider experience would classify 
the whale as a mammal; but in the context of a narrower ex- 
perience, the whale is truly a fish. Bosanquet is insisting here 
that our knowledge of nature is in sort geographical, and that 
the extension of science by new and often strange hypotheses 
does not really discredit the older and narrower hypotheses 
which are displaced. It was true that the sun moves round the 
earth; it is true that the earth moves round the sun. Some such 
view, apparently self-contradictory, is implied in every absolute 
and nonempirical realism; for this doctrine ultimately requires 
the literal identity of ideas with things. 

Idealistic philosophers made use of a distinction between 
extemd and internal relations. If the relations discovered by 
the intellect are “external” to the things related, then some of 
the relations of a thing may be correctly knovm even while we 
are ignorant of others. Thus you may know that your friend 
has an older brother, but be unaware that he has a younger 
sister. If all relations are “internal,” however, then real ac- 
quaintance with anything, i.e. knowledge of its character, in- 
cludes knowledge of all its relations. Knowing your friend, 
you know he has a aster. It is clear, perhaps, that for common 
sense and empirical science, the distinction between external 
and internal relations cannot be ultimate. We proceed as if re- 
lations were external, discovering now this and now that causal 
or other connection, as best we can. It is in the light of these 
causal relations, however, that we progressively define the 
character of a thing, so that the relations which initially were 
external are finally internal. Thus we study a salt, discern its 
color, its specific crystalline form, etc.; but we fail to determine 
from these data its solubility. We discover by experiment that 
it dissolves in any acid; and from this “external” relationship 
we learn something of its internal constitution, so that the re- 
lation becomes “intemaL” The absolute idealist holds all rela- 



the nineteenth century 


42 X 

ingly than any of his critics the inherent weakness of absolute 
idealism. But discussion of this new realism belongs to our 
review of contemporary thought. 

Looking back over this summary of nineteenth-century 
philosophy, we find little that is important and philosophically 
new. The thinker rings the changes of eighteenth-century 
thought, usually with less vitality than his more creative pred- 
ecessors. Where reflection starts from Kant, there is a fatal 
development of “Neo-Fichteans,” “Neo-Schellings,” and “Neo- 
Hegelians.” Where the thinker starts from Hume, he may 
either be led to discover Kant, or flounder into a verbal posi- 
tivism that really returns to a rationalistic metaphysics dis- 
guised as an absolutistic “methodology.” There were at least 
two good reasons for this intellectual failture. The first was that 
the problem which faced this age baffled the inquirer. Mathe- 
matical physics, loyal to the mechanical principles of the New- 
tonian physics, seemed to indicate the dependence of science 
upon absolute mathematical axioms; and this discouraged a 
radical and consistent empiricism; yet, on the other hand, 
science everywhere, no less in physical inquiry than elsewhere, 
proceeded from observed data to large hypothesis, and in this 
way affirmed its empirical faith in the ultimacy of particular 
fact. The nineteenth century lacked the data dlowing escape 
from this deadlock; and the profoundest and only completely 
honest thinkers were, perhaps, those who saw this problem as 
Kant had seen it, and accepted Kant’s phenomenalism or posi- 
tivism with respect to natural knowledge, and his noumendism 
or moral realism with respect to action. Fortunately the twen- 
tieth century was to provide the data freeing human thought 
from this impasse. 

The other reason for the failure of philosophical genius was 
the shift of public interest from philosophy to science, and, 
after the mid-century, to the mind-shattering hypothesis of 
evolution. It was in empirical inquiry that the genius of the 
nineteenth century exhibited its power. Never had there been 



the nineteenth century 423 

English Utilitarianism, New York, The Macmillan Com- 
pany, 1902). 

7. Spencer, H., Works available in most libraries. See especially 

his First Prmciples, New York, D. Appleton-Century, and 
his “preface” to Collin’s Epitome of Spencer’s Philosophy. 

8. Sidgwick, H., The Ethics of Green, Spencer and Martineau. 

New York, The Macmillan Company, 1902. 

9. Ward, J., Naturalism and Apiosticism. London, A. and C 

Black, 1915. 

10. Watson, W., Comte, Mill, and Spencer. Glasgow, J. Maclehose 
and Sons, 1895. 

Other studies of Spencer by Hudson, Macpherson, Royce, 
Taylor, Thompson, Harrison. 

n. Green, T. H., “Introduction to Hume,” in Treatise on Human 
Nature, David Hume, London and New York, Longmans, 
Green and Company, 1875. 

12. Prolegomena to Ethics. London and New York, Oxford 

University Press, 1883. 

ij. Principles of Political Obligation. Boston, Longmans, 

Green and Company, 1895. 

Studies of Green by Fairbrother, Johnson, Sidgwick, Muir- 
head (in The Service of the State, Man versus the State as a 
Present Issue, London, G. Allen and Unwin), Ritchie (in 
Prmciples of State Interference, London, Social Science 
Series, 1891), MacCunn {op. cit.). 

14. Bradley, F. H., Principles of Logic. London and New York, 

Oxford University Press, 1883. 

15. Bradley, F. H., Appearance and Reality. New York, The Mac- 

millan Company, 1902. 

16. Essays on Truth and Reality. London and New York, 

Oxford University Press, 1914. 

17. Rashdall, H., The Metaphysics of Bradley. London, Gerald 

Duckworth and Company. 

18. Bosanquet, B., The Principle of Individuality and V,alue. New 

York, The Macmillan Company, 1912. 

19. The Value and Destiny of the Individttal. New York, 

The Macmillan Company, 1913. 

20. The Meeting of Extremes in Contemporary Philosophy, 

New York, The Macmillan Company, 1921. 



22 THE CONCEPT OF EVOLUTION 
IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 


In ANTiQumr, anaxtmander and empedocles 
advanced evolutionary hypotheses which were evi- 
dently based upon study of the organic species. Early Greek 
science was as much concerned to understand the generation 
or evolution of nature as to learn something of the permanent 
structure of nature. Science was usually presented, indeed, as 
an inquiry into the -physis, i.e. into the coming-to-be or gen- 
eration of nature. Today the word “physical” carries no such 
evolutionary connotation, and this change of meaning testifid j 
to a radical change of interest and outlook. Perhaps by Pytha-# 
oras, certainly by Parmenides and Plato, scientific interest d(sl 
focused upon the constant structure or morphology of n!ho^ 
and the historical or evolutionary character of natureer'" 
henceforth neglected. This neglect of natural history w; ^ 
quired by the ever clearer distincdon of theoretical or sya^^ 
atic knowledge from more casual knowledge, which dii* ^ 
aim at theoretical unity; and it was encouraged by the ir^f; ’ 
ing dependence of analysis upon mathematical the-^1*^*^^ 
other words, the development of mathematical 
vented the development of a science centered upoir^^^S^'^^^ 



the concept of evolution in science and philosophy 427 

appreciation finally became explicit in the concept of human 
progress. Although given a name only in the late eighteenth 
century, the concept of progress underlay and supported the 
whole development of modem science and society. Science 
was conceived to be the intellectual wedge which opened the 
way to political and other progress; and no institution nor 
system Im yet been able to rob modem man of this optimistic 
oudook upon an expanding and progressive future. 

But it was seldom seen, and it stiU is inadequately understood, 
that this conception of human progress commits us to a tem- 
poralistic or historical conception of nature at large. Quite 
illogically — if by “law” we refer to the fixed and definable 
principles of nature — ^men spoke of a “law of progress.” By an 
inherent natural necessity, said the first advocates of progress, 
man has continuously progressed in wisdom, goodness, and 
power. This is, of course, untrae. Human decline is unfor- 
tunately as evident as human progress; and it is clear that 
progress depends first upon the human will to progress, and 
ultimately upon a number of factors into the nature of which 
we would do well to inquire. 

The philosophical systems elaborated during the kte eight- 
eenth and early nineteenth century show a curious half-aware- 
ness of history, a sort of effort to accept, without explicitly 
acknowledging, their mental orientation upon histoti(^ and 
evolutionary fact. We have seen how the post-Kantian dia^ 
lectidans, and the systems of Comte and Spencer, tried to d^* 
justice to the largest consequences of natural evolution withoV^ 
accepting the hypothesis of evolution itself. And, in a deer 
manner, the whole development of thought from Hume 
Kant onwards prepared the way for an evolutionary view 
nature. Both Hume and Kant made time, not space, the w? 
and mott ultimate category of knowledge. Reiity, this 
mean, is in the last resort a linear, progressive sort of 1 "'^’ith 
But aitbongh these two thinkers were somewhat skeptic^’^^s®^'^® 
ceming theoretical knowledge, they did not explic^o^offic^^ 



the concept of evolution in science and philosophy 


429 

This Aristotelian doctrine, either directly or through its in- 
corporation into Platonism, soon elevated the fixity of species 
into a primary dogma of the human intellect. 

For ourselves, recently emancipated from this dogma, even 
a cursory study of the species of plant and animal life points to 
the fact of organic evolution. Why else should the species fall 
into a natural classification which takes on the form of a 
genealogical tree? By the close of the eighteenth century, there 
was ample and conclusive evidence for the hypothesis of 
geologic and organic evolutioiL Yet the hypothesis was stoutly 
resisted or even contemptuously dismissed, often by sincere 
and competent scientists. These irreconcilables felt, obscurely 
but correctly, that the evolutionary hypothesis contravened 
certain fundamental assumptions accepted by earlier science; 
and they feared that it would discredit the whole achievement 
of science, and invalidate its method. So they rebuked or ig- 
nored Lamarck, who first gathered the evidence for evolution 
into a unified and really conclusive argument. Condemnation 
of the Lamarckian hypothesis was the easier, because Lamarck 
gave to his exposition an Aristotelian and vitalistic interpreta- 
tion. The mutation of species, he said, is the consequence or 
manifestation of a vital force inherent in the organism, which 
in its pursuit of existence may develop new characters trans- 
mitted to its progeny. The biologist rejected this view, because 
it implied that organic changes are self-caused. This would 
violate the principle basic to mechanistic causal analysis, which 
holds all change to be reaction to some external action or 
condition. 

Half a century later, in 1859, the scientific world generally 
applauded the publication of Charles Darwin’s Origin of 
Species, although there persisted some minor opposition to its 
teaching. During the interval between Lamarck and Darwin, 
geologists like Lyell and Hutton had familarized scientists with 
the evidence provided by fossil remains of the progressive 
evolution of the earth’s surface. Darwin used this geological 



the concept of evolution in science and philosophy 433 

velopment was distinguished by its emphatic aflSrmation of the 
reality of individual being and the ultimacy of particular fact, 
and by its opposition to a rationalism which affirmed the reality 
of universal being and the absoluteness of universal principles. 
To say that individual being is real is to say that individual 
being is effective, or truly and finally determinative of what 
happens in the world. And to say that universals are abstrac- 
tions is to say that universal being is ineffective, unreal, ficti- 
tious. But the structural principles, supposedly effective in 
keeping ^ecies fixed, were universal principles, definitive some- 
how of universal being; and if there is no universal being, the 
structural principles are not effective, and we know of nothing 
which might fixate the species and types of things. To be con- 
sistent, we must attribute this mutability of specific form also 
to inorganic nature. We cannot conceive of organic evolution 
falfing place in a nonevolving cosmos. Yet against all this reas- 
oning is the argument that science, even an historical or evolu- 
tionary science, seems to depend upon the affirmation of con- 
stants, structural principles, theoretical formulatitHis — ^in a 
word some form and some degree of realistic rationalism. A 
nature that is exclusively individual, wholly unspecific, and 
incorrigibly fluent could never, it would seem, be known nor 
intellectually vmderstood. 

We will engage this problem in our concluding chapter. 
Now we turn to certain philosophical speculations which are 
important not for their solution of the problem, but for their 
growing rect^niticm of it, and for their oversharp statement 
of it. 

Only in the closing decade of the nineteenth century do we 
find thinkers who perceived the more radical implications of 
evolutionary science. One of the first of these was Nietzsche. 
Friedrich Nietzsche ( 1844-1900) is in ill repute today, at least 
in democratic society; for he was the proponent of the doc- 
trine of the supermm, a doctrine which undoubtedly helped to 
inspire the creators of Nazi Germany. It might be argued that 



THE OONCEirr OP EVOLUTION IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 


4J5 

But he gives the doctrine an evolutionary twist, in that he 
portrays the heroic and aristocratic radividual as the protagonist 
of a new mutation of the human species, bringing into existence 
the “superman.” We remember how Schopenhauer depicted 
sexual passion as the involuntary servitude of the individual to 
the ends of the species. Now Nietzsche, a generation after 
Darwin, suggests that the amoral “hero” enthrones himself in 
order to establish a new species, and to fulfil the design of a 
cosmic evolution. 

To understand Nietzsche’s error, we should appreciate his 
half-truth. He is telling us that the will of man is the dynamo 
of his creative evolution, productive of new and higher forms 
of existence. Moral insight, like scientific insight, must break 
through and progressively widen the formulated codes of the 
past. Morality too must evolve. We may forgive Nietzsche 
his indictment of Christian civilization and his caricature of 
Christian morality, when we learn what a flaccid, formalized, 
sepulchral “Chrisrianity” surrounded the boy Nietzsche in 
his father’s parsonage. We can also understand Nietzsche when 
he sanctifies only one virtue, that of courage; for courage is 
most needed by those who would themselves pursue and in 
others arouse a living faith. What we cannot excuse in Nietzsche 
is his moral snobbishness, his contempt for humanity. Stupid 
provincialism, from which in his superficial coanopolitanism 
he fled, still blinded him to all but an obscure Greek episode 
of the human past. He had no large prospect upon man’s 
moral progress. Nietzsche, an obscure and lonely neurotic, 
spent his last years in an asylum for the mentally diseased. 
That did not prevent the propagation of his equivocal gospel, 
which was couched in as luminous a prose as the German lan- 
guage has produced. Symptomatic of a mind diseased, perhaps, 
was the cult which looked to Nietzsche for its medicine. 

Nietzsche’s doctrme is philosophically noteworthy for its 
affirmation of radical disaintinuity in nature. Human progress, 
it implies, proceeds by inexplicable leaps from an older pattern 



THE CONCEPT OF EVOLUTION IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 


437 

donary, genetic, historical form of knowledge. The tran- 
scendentalism to which Fichte and Hegel gave a rationalistic 
form, and to which Schopenhauer gave an aesthetic formula- 
tion, becomes in Nietzsche a sheer anti-intellectualism, a volun- 
tarism unmediated and unmoderated by anything whatsoever. 
The will, void of scruple and intelligible direction, must carve 
its destiny. It is this sheer voluntarism, this abandonment to the 
paroxysm of actio.n, which became the false strength and 
deeper weakness of Germany. Blind to the world about it, 
Germany refused all adjustment to its environment, and gave 
to its neighbors the alternatives of destroying, or being de- 
stroyed by, a people gone berserk. Nietzsche might have 
learned from the Greeks that whom the gods would destroy 
they first make mad. There is moral sanity, one and the same 
forever. 

A curious doctrine of Nietzsche’s, but one which casts light 
upon his limitations, is his revival of the Greek cyclicism. 
Everything that happens, he wrote, is the fatal return of what 
has ^eady transpired an infinite number of times; and it is 
the mark of the heroic superman that he can contemplate this 
eternal recurrence without losing his reason. In this fantasy 
we see a ccntradictcry return to the etemalistic and univcrsal- 
istic outlook which in his main doctrine he emphatically re- 
nounces. He intimates, that is to say, that the new insight of 
the “superman” is just that comprehension of all time and 
space which Plato had accorded to the reason. 

Henri Bergson (1859-1941) is a philosopher of evolution 
who has seized the other horn of the dilemma presented by 
the fact of evolution. If we agree that nature radically evolves, 
so that even the most basic structures of nature arc subject to 
temporal change, shall we suppose with Nietzsche that nature 
jumps by a transcendental act from one structural block in 
the moving evolution to another; or shall we, as Bergson ad- 
vises, make no appeal to structural knowledge, but tty instead 
to understand the evolutionary progress as sheer motion, or 



THE CaSCEVT OF EVOLUTION IN SCIENCE AND PHUUSOPHY 439 

tiality for art. Tom in his youth between poetry and philoso- 
phy, he made philosophy his career; but he allowed to poetry 
its revenge, in that he used philosophical analysis to discredit 
theoretical knowledge in the interest of art and aesthetic in- 
tuition. 

This invidious teaching was not without antecedents in post- 
Kantian philosophy, which was now widespread. Bergson 
gives to the post-Knntian criticism of science, especially to the 
pragmatic positivism first enunciated by Schopenhauer, a new 
and incisive formulation. The theoretical intellect, he writes, 
is not a cognitive faculty motivated by a desire to know nature 
and intent upon a faithful description of nature. The theoreti- 
cal intellect serves practical ends. It developed as an agency of 
survival, and its function is to provide some practical control 
of our environment. Nature is incorrigibly individual, its every 
item is unique and incomparable; but the theoretical intellect 
gra^s only those aspects of fact which recur again and again, 
and in the recurrence or prevention of which we are vkaily 
interested. Bergson suggests, indeed, that the intellect does not 
so much discover these constant or recurrent characters within 
nature as construct than and project them into nature, therd>y 
obscuring the true individual pattern of natural occurrence. 
Theoretical knowledge, he concludes, really tells us tmly about 
our own organic needs. It is incorrigibly subjective and de- 
ceptive. 

Something like this conclusion had been implicit in modern 
philosophy ever since Hume and Kant attempted to etplain 
how knowledge arises as the result of mental process. Bergson’s 
study of this constructive process is unusually penetrating. 
Earlier epistemology, he points out, had confused the category 
of time with one of the three dimensions of space. Time was 
conceived as a linear order of instants, by analogy with space 
which was conceived to be a three-dimensional order of por- 
tions. But in tmth no such homology or similarity exists be- 
tween time and space, because time is irreversible. Time is every- 



THE CX 3 NCEPT OF EVOLtmON IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 44I 

condnuous change. Mathematical science is today equipped to 
deal with the fact of continuity — ^it is able to define the contin- 
uous line, surface, volume, motion, change. It is only this 
mathematical grasp of continuity, indeed, that allows us to ap- 
preciate and to dKcribe exactly what is discontinuous in nature. 
Yet Bergson tells us that natural science replaces the continu- 
ous evolution of nature by a calculating machine, made up of 
jointed parts which creak and jerk in a mimicry of nature 
that is caricature or satire, not truth. It is because he caricatures 
theoretical science that Bergson must prefer art to science, 
which is truly the greatest of human arts. 

Bergson’s studies are rich in incidental insights. In his 
thoughtful Matter and Mermry he compares the intellect to 
a grid, which allows to enter our minds only those elements of 
“pure perception” which are practically relevant to our vital 
needs in responding to the given situation. Because the mind 
automatically preserves in memory every past perception, this 
grid must suppress those memories which arc irrelevant to the 
present situation. Thus the intellect acts as mediator between 
the inexhaustible materials of “pure perception” and our simi- 
larly inexhaustible personal memory. Science arises at the in- 
tersection of environmental get^aphy and personal history. 
This conception, although unnecessarily subjectivistic, sug- 
gests its own expansion in a new understanding of the relation- 
ship between time and space. Bergson, it seems, would emanci- 
pate both “pure perception” and memory from the intellectual 
grid; and Proust, Joyce, and other “stream of consciousness” 
novelists inspired by Bergson show us the consequence of this 
emancipation in an art which, whatever its surface iridesceneer 
seems to lack purpose and plot. 

Bergson’s hest-known work is his Creative Evolution, a 
metaphysical study of the facts of organic evolution. This 
study is prejudiced by Bergson’s earlier dismissal of theoretical 
science as a perjured and deceptive accoimt of physical nature; 
for Bergson caimot now do justice to the causal connection 



THB CONCEPT OF EVOLUTION IN SaENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 445 

every creative hypothesis. Bergson identifies science with the 
scientific formulas generated by the creative scientific mind, 
formulas which any mediocre mind can memorize and mechani- 
cally apply. This error may in its turn have been due to Berg- 
son’s narrow conception of intuition, which he identified with 
perception. We need not suppose that immediate perception 
is our whole intuition of truth, and that we possess, in addition 
to this perceptual faculty, only a power of verbal classification 
and abstraction. Knowledge is advanced by large intuition 
suggesting new hypothesis, this latter being the source of all 
descriptive theory. Somehow we must rehabilitate our real 
faculty of cognition, the true and creative “intuition” which is 
the generator of all science and all true art. 

In his ripest study. The Two Sources of Morality and Re- 
lipon, Bergson is more sober. He finds two distinct factors 
working in social evolution. One is the moral insight which has 
inspired the great teachers and prophets; the other is the codes 
and institutions which preserve and apply these prophetic in- 
sights. His fantastic proposal to syntheize the instinct of 
insects with the theoretical intellect now reappears in the wise 
proposal that we should deliberately bring a critical moral in- 
sight to bear upon our social institutions, continuously reform- 
ing and ultimately transforming these. So the most brilliant 
Jewish thinker of his century would once again reconcile the 
law with the prophets, and fulfil the law in an ampler iusticc. 

As the Nazis exploited Nietzsche, so the teachings of Berg- 
son have been exploited by reactionary polidcal opportunists, 
who read into his intuitionism the i'ostificstion of a violent 
actmsme, and who use his pragmatism to justify the abuse of 
institutional mechanisms and orthodox loyalties. Much as the 
Greek sophists prostituted the critical method of Greek science, 
by transforming it into a cheap and scurrilous diatribe against 
“convention” and morality, so these modem sensationalists have 
cheapened the modem criticism of science, by converting it 
into an apology for amoralism and social violence. 



THE OONCEPT OF EVOLUTION IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 


445 

his estimate of history, however, Croce is misled by his sub- 
jective idcalisir.. which does not allow him to distinguish his- 
tory as it occurred in the past from history as it is recovered 
by the present mmd. He is misled also by his expressionism, 
which holds every product of mental activity, including writ- 
ten history, to be only an expression of the mind which pro- 
duced it. ^ Croce tells us that the materials of history, i.e. the 
data recovered by historical research, do not constitute history 
until they are organized, synthesized, and informed by the liv- 
ing mmd of the historian. It is only here and now, in its actual 
entertainment by some mind, that the past has reality. What 
therefore is the past.^ It is a dimension of the present mind, 
which somehow projects its own distinctive form as “the past.” 
Our ordinary conception of the past is in this case diametrically 
opposite to the truth. We think of the past as determining the 
present, whereas in truth the present determines the past. More 
correctly, history is the full realization of our present selves. 
The essential work of mind, i.e. of absolute being, is the con- 
tinual reformation of its historical retrospect, and a perpetual 
rewriting of history. 

It is questionable whether a subjectivism so extreme as 
Croce’s does not collapse into meaninglessness. We ordinarily 
suppose that the documents and other data used by the his- 
torian actually preserve certain characters pt^sessed by them 
when they originated. W^e believe that we read the very words 
inscribed by Caesar in his remote encampment, or dictated by 
Queen Elizabeth. But no, Croce tells us; your perception of 
the document is a present perception, is it not? And similarly 
your interpretation of the document is a present hypothesis? 
What is there here that is past? There is only your present 
mind, which generates that “past.” But if we accept this con- 
clusion as true and sufHcient, what meaning can we give to 
the words “history,” “the past,” “yesterday,” “tomorrow.” 
Time evidendy demands more objective treatment — Croce’s 
violent embrace destroys its object. 



THE CONCEPT OF EVOLUTION IN SQENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 447 

not manifest, in its particular way, some general or even uni- 
versal principle? Would it not be paradoxical if the hypothesis 
of evolution, which is the largest possible application of the 
conviction that what occurs later is the causal resultant of what 
existed earlier, should finally invalidate the concept of causa- 
tion on which it rests? 

The mechanistic concept of causation, which requires later 
occurrence to be exhaustively explained as the determinate 
effect of earlier occurrence, has been the governing principle 
of modem science, and it has been the anchor since time im- 
memorial of common sense and human sanity. We can really 
conceive of no other son of explanation of fact. All that has 
ever pretended to be another son of explanation cither col- 
lapses upon careful examination into nonsense, or reveals it- 
self to be only a verbal disguise of mechanistic explanation. 
Thus philosophers long spoke of teleological explanation, by 
which they meant an explanation of earlier occurrence as being 
somehow determined by what it brought to pass later. We 
cannot avoid this sort of explanation in our dealings with con- 
scious and purposive behavior. The reason or cause of a pur- 
posive act, we are wont to say, is the future effect which it in- 
tends. And so, the tcleologist argued, we may suppose every 
occurrence, and finally the whole cosmic process, to be de- 
termined by that last supreme event which is its ultimate issue. 
The future explains the past; and it does this only because it 
determines the past, of which it is the reason or cause. But the 
scientist, faithful to his principle of mechanistic causation, will 
easily elude this argument for teleology in nature. The state- 
ment that purposive behavior is determined by the end which 
it seeks to realize, he will say, is elliptical. The purpose does 
envisage an end, and action is guided by that prospect; yet the 
purpose, the prospea, and the end envisaged are themselves 
already determinate, and determined in fact by past conditions. 
Purposive behavior is thus only a peculiarly complicated sort of 
mechanistically determined activity. 



THE CONCUEPT OF EVOLUTION IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 

termined at some first moment, or that everything is determined 
by its last issue. Hume’s conclusion still stands — ^we know of 
no universal necessity in nature. Every moment is real and 
effective, not only the first or last moment; and the later mo- 
ment is no less effective than the earlier moment. 

Now the hypothesis of evolution exhibits this truth, first 
glimpsed by Hume, in a striking and tremendous way. We dis- 
cover on this planet a progressive mutation of natural form 
from inorganic, through organic, to human character. There 
is material continuity in this progress, the inorganic matter 
becoming organic, and organic matter becoming human. We 
are required, therefore, to seek some sort of causal explanation 
of the progress; and it is this explanation which eludes our 
philosophers of evolution and drives them to speculative frenzy. 
Nietzsche concludes that the evolutionary mutation is inex- 
plicable, that it is externally unconditioned, and that we can 
therefore mutate into anything we please. Bergson concludes 
that evolutionary change is explicable, but only by a sort of 
explanation that eludes scientific statement and that finds its 
expression in the symbolisms of art. Croce concludes, astonish- 
ingly, that the very distinction between past and present, upon 
which all causal explanation rests, must be renounced, in which 
case, of course, thg problem disappears; but this means only 
that we are proh, |ted from asking any intelligent question 
concerning natural -..hange. 

One more “philosopher of evolution” will help us to grasp 
the nature of this problem, presented by evolutionary science. 
Sanruel Alexander (bom 1859) seems to have been early in- 
fluenced by the dialectic of Hegel, but to have refused Hegel’s 
idealistic epistemology. He is realistic in his acceptance of the 
theories of natural science; and he makes his chief concern the 
progress of natural evolution, especially in its movement from 
physical or inorganic matter toward organic form, and finally 
toward human intelligence. 

In his chief work, which is entitled Space, Time, and Deity, 



THE C»NCEPT OE EVOLUTIOV IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 45 1 

overreaching or indwelling Form, working upon nature and 
ptrsuadir.g it into that form “as far as necessity allovre”; but 
:;.c forms of sensate, organic, minded, and deific nature 

arise spontaneously— or rather, given certain complications 
of the earlier form, the later form its thereby also present; and 
here we are reminded of Spencer, who taught that the organic 
and human forms of nature are nothing else than progressively 
complex distributions of matter. These sudden and inexplicable 
appearances of new forms or qualities Alexander calls “emer- 
gences,” and he exhorts us to accept “with natural piety” this 
potentiality of matter to re-create itself in new forms. “Natural 
piety,” it would seem, requires a moratorium on inquiry and 
curiosity. It is just the nature of nature, we are told, to evolve, 
and to evolve specifically yet urprcdictcbly into the mineral, 
organic, human, and social forms which we observe. Alexander 
does suggest the effective and universal presence in nature of 
a certain “nisus,” ue. a tendency or direction, leading from 
forms of less value to forms of more value. This nisus, a sort 
of ghost of the Platonic Good or the Hegelian Absolute, 
escapes definition, and is presumably the object of a tran- 
scendental apprehension. We have here a mystical conclusion, 
similar to that of Bradley. 

Alexander’s system is valuable for its clear presentation of 
the problem it undertakes to solve- If we accept the analyses 
and results of die several theoretical sciences as a final and 
definitive description of nature, it fe shown, then we must 
admit the effective presence in nature of relationships and 
changes which simply elude theoretical explanation- Theoreti- 
cal physics defines physical structure, theoretical chemistry 
defines chemical structure, theoretical biology defines organic 
structure, theoretical psychology defines human nature, and 
theoretical sociology define, as they eventuate, the activi- 
ties which Alexander attributes to “deity.” But no theoretical 
analysis will grasp the evolutionary changes which transform 
physical motion into chemical interaction, this into organic 



THE CONCEPT OF EVOLUTION IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 455 

plicable. And third, the doctrine of emergence only revives 
the discredited fallacies of rationalistic philosophy. It revives 
in its hypostatization of primary and secondary caclities the 
Cartesian dualism; but it proceeds to widen this dualism into 
an absolute pluralism, by adding tertiary and quaternary quali- 
ties. Yet we know of many causal relations between physical 
actions and organic reactions, between physi'rlcgica! conditions 
and mental processes, between individual thought and its social 
environment. Why should we rrhrtrzri'.v insist that causal rela- 
tions are intelligible when they occur viithin physical, organic, 
mental, and social processes, but unintelligible when they occur 
between these processes? Science cannot respect so arbitrary a 
distinction. 

And finally, when we examine more closely this doctrine of 
emergentism, we discover that it is only a rather belated recog- 
nition, obscured by rationalistic prepossessions, of the truth 
announced by Hume. Hume showed that no causal connection 
is intelligible in the sense that the effect can be deduced from 
the cause. In all causal analysis, we finally reach types of causal 
sequence which just are, and which we must accept as the way 
of the world, as the basis of all scientific explanation of par- 
ticular occurrences and as the source of our definitions of 
things. But this finality of causal coimection holds of all causal 
connections, not only of some. If the causal effect by which a 
physical object stimulates in ourselves a mental perception is 
inexplicable and “emergent,” so is the causal connccrion by 
which a physical object influences the motion of another physi- 
cal object. This even the seventeenth-century Occasionalists 
knew. But Alexander cither does not understand, or will not 
accept, the demonstration of Hume that all causal proces 
whatsoever is “emergent” in its contingency. He is really a 
belated Ctoiesian, lost in an evolving world. He teUs us that 
there are four or five absolute substances, namely physical 
motion, chemical matter, organic matter, mind, and society. 
He admits that the earlier substance produces the latter. But 
he rr.tir.rc.!ist:ca!!y identifies science with an intuition of abso- 



THE CONCEPT OF EVOLUTION IN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 455 

may insist here that we cannot legitimately accept the common 
conclusion of these “'ch:!';?onhers of evolution,” who tell us 
that cvoluticnary progress is scientifically inexplicable because 
it eludes a purely theoretical analysis. Science is not necessarily 
limited to theoretical analysis; nor, as we shall show, has it ever 
been so limited. Science has always been more than its the- 
oretical descriptions; and only because this is so could it arrive 
at and seriously entertain the hj^othesis of natural evolution. 
Science is eternally committed, however, to the principle that 
all natural occurrence whatsoever is causally determinate, and 
therefore scientifically intelligible and explicable. If we will 
only hold fast to this principle of sufficient causation, which is 
the root of human sanit)’-, we may come through the dark 
forest of intellectual confusion and know again the light of 
reason. 


Notes for Further Reading 

1. Frazer, J. G., Condor cet on the Progress of the Human Mind) 

London and New York, Oxford University Press, 1933. 

2. Morley of Blackburn, J., Biographical Studies (Turgot, Con- 

dorcet). New York, TTie Macmillan Company, 1923. 

3. Bun?-, J. B., The Idea of Progress. New York, The Macmillan 

Company, 1921, 1932. 

4. Dewey, J., The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy. New York, 

Henry Holt and Company, 1910. 

5. Osborn, H. F., The Origin and Evolution of Life. New York, 

Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1917. 

6. Morgan, C. L., Emergent Evolution. New York, Henry Holt 

and Company, 1923, 

7. Boodin, J. E., Cosmic Evolution. New York, The Macmillan 

Company, 1925. 

8. Hobhouse, L. T., Development and Purpose. New York, The 

Macmillan Company, 1913. 

9. Baitsell, S. H., ed. The Evolution of Earth and Man. New 

Haven, Yale University Press, 1929. 

10. Conger, S. P., New Vievos of Evolution. New York, The Mac- 
millan Company, 1929. 



CONTEAffiORARY PHILOSOPHY 


n 



23 REALISM 


W NOW REACH THE END OF OTJR SURVEY AND 

approach the goal for which we undertook it, 
namely, an understanding of contemporary life and thought. 
Some of the thinkers noticed in the preceding chapter are 
either still living or only recently deceased; and certain of the 
nineteenth-century movements earlier described are still influ- 
ential, although usually in somewhat modified form. Our study 
of these thinkers and movements accordingly already intro- 
duces us to contempOTary thought. Yet there is a sense in which 
the twentieth century, especially the period following the First 
World War, has drawn a line between ourselves and earlier 
^culation. Contemporary philosophy makes new starts in 
new directions. This independent and rather revolutionary 
attitude affects the way in which earlier doctrines are under- 
stood and developed today; and we best appreciate the new 
outlook by observing those contemporary movements which arc 
still in process of formulating their doctrines, and which brii^ 
this outlook to sharpest expression. We will consider the move- 
ments known as the new realism, pragmatism, and logical poa- 
tivism; but it should be remembered that every such classifica- 
tion is oversimple and somewhat misleading. Today the whole 
pattern of traditional thought is undergoing a sort of kaleido- 

459 



BEAXtSM 


461 

metaphysical pretensions; but the idealists transformed this 
criticism into an invalidation of science, in the interests of a 
supcrscientific metaphysics. The scientist who is intent upon 
particular fact, it was urged, reaches only a tentative, con- 
jectural, and incorrigibly partial or fragmentary knowledge; 
but the reflective philosopher carries the stumbluig and blink- 
ered effort of science to its true goal in an unrestricted knowl- 
edge of absolute, universal, and unitary being. Only in such 
absolute knowledge do we find the complete interrelationship 
of fact which science haltingly depicts in its empirical hypoth- 
eses. Perhaps we may agree that science does point beyond 
its present formulations of fact to a more inclusive knowledge. 
But the scientist would like to advance to this better knowl- 
edge himself, with due regard for scientific method and rigor. 
He is not satisfied to be told that his method is by defini- 
tion incompetent, and that another “transcendental” knowl- 
edge, which he would call empty and verbal, must supersede 
his empirical study of fact. So science was increasingly and 
quite properly hostile to this philosophical transcendentalism. 

Further, the political implications of this absolutistic philos- 
ophy aroused fear and distrust, especially when it became the 
creed of conservative opposition to a liberalism which seemed 
to have lost its intellectual bearings. Starring from the ap- 
parently innocuous and liberal-sounding doctrine of individual 
self-realization, the absolutist could pMtray this self-realization 
as a movement by which the individual person ultimately iden- 
tifies himself with Absolute Reality, the One or All, and 
proceed to discover the chief actualization of this Absolute in 
the state. This conclusion may appear farfetched; yet it is his- 
torical fact that all absolutistic political theory has grounded 
itself upon some form of absolutistic metaphysics. 

Finally, the doctrine of metaphysical absolutism, even where 
it was ostensibly advanced as the theological bastion of religion, 
repelled many a religious mind and probably contravened the 
creeds of most religious confessions. Christianity cspedaliy 



REAUSM 463 

ism, and other movements which hold that the mind in somo 
way constructs and in some degree generates its cognized 
objects. The doctrine is indeed realistic in its insistence upon 
the identity of cognized things, relationships 

— ^with reality itself. Yet the name “realism” is not very helpful 
to our appreciation of its distinctive teaching. Medieval scho- 
lasticism was realistic when it taught that the reason intuits the 
true essences or specific forms of things. Nominalism was real- 
istic in respect to sensed fact, if it insisted that our immediate 
perceptions of particular character, but not our abstract con- 
ceptions, infallibly apprehend reality. And absolute idealism 
in Hegel or Bosanquet was realistic when it accorded to the 
concepts generated by transcendental reflection an absolute 
validity and an identity of some hind with universal being. The 
idealistic postulate of absolute idealism, aflirming the identity 
of Reality with Mind, was used to establish the realistic postu- 
late that the objects construaed by mind may have the status 
of absolute reality. In what, then, did this new realism distin- 
guish itself from older forms of realism? W herein was it more 
realistic than these other doctrines? The new realism distin- 
guished itself from earlier realism in two ways. First, it was 
impartial with respect to the realistic claims of perception and 
conception, or, the senses and the inteUect. Both, it held, may 
directly and truly apprehend real bemg of some sort. Secondly, 
it was unusually clear and outspoken concerning the nature 
of such cognition. The perceived or conceived object, it said, 
enters the mind without alteration of any kind, without shadow 
of change. Cognition differs from many processes known to 
us, in that the cognized objea is unaffected by its mental con- 
text, or by the process of becoming cognized. The object as it 
is apprehended is exactly what it was before it was appre- 
hended, and what it will be after it is out of mind again. 

A primary intention of this doctrine was to protect scientific 
knowledge from the various kinds of criticism it had under- 
gone smoe Berkeley and Hume. If both perceptien and con- 



REALISM 


465 

proponent of contemporary realism, is Bertrand Russell (bom 
1872). Russell in his successive writings has attempted such 
diverse approaches to the problem of knowledge, and reached 
so various and tentative conclusions, that a resume of his teach- 
ing is scarcely possible. Noticeable is his distinction, both in his 
earliest and in his latest writings, of two domains of “real” 
knowledge, i.e. of absolute and necessary judgments. One of 
these is the perceptual domain of sensed quality. We indubi- 
tably perceive colors, shades of the “same” color, and relation- 
ship among colors. Orange is necessarily placed between red 
and yellow. Here is the domain of indubitable, immediately 
apprehended fact which provides the material — ^not only in its 
qualities but also in its rc! itionsfirr s — 5 .:r all conceptual knowl- 
edge. The other domain is that of logical and conceptual 
objects, e.g. mathematical entities. Here also we have imme- 
diate and indubitable insight. The problem is to see how these 
two domains of absolute knowledge, which appear in many 
ways incommensurable, conspire to give us the hypotheticii 
or probable knowledge which is empirical science. Russell 
attacks this problem again and again, but never claims that he 
has solved it. 

Russell’s lasting fame, which will increase as the centuries 
pass, depends less on these inconclusive epistemological studies 
than on his reform of l(^c, to which we referred in our study 
of Kant. For more than two thousand years, logic had re- 
mained much what Aristotle left it — a study of sentences of the 
form A is B (all A is B, some A is B, no A is B, some A is not 
B) and of syllogisms composed of pairs of such sentences and 
their implications (no AisB, some C is A, so some C is not B). 
Philosophically minded logicians had produced large tomes 
which elaborated this primitive logic as a basic definition of the 
“laws of thought,” and discussed with some acumen and vast 
labor its relationship to factual matei^ and , ultimate being. 
But modem science had long since forgotten .this Aristotelian 
logic, and developed its own ways of thought and intellectual 



REAUSM 


467 

the logic of the future. It transformed the discipline of logic, 
vastly extended it, and made possible a new understanding of 
the nature of logic and of its relation to empirical knowledge 
and to fact. 

This revolution was not the work of a day, nor yet of two 
men. Russell leaned heavily on the contributions of earlier 
mathematicians and logicians, such as Leibniz, Frege, Peano, 
and Boole; but he consolidated and developed these earlier 
studies, and, above all, he made the intellectual world aware of 
them and their significance. The Matbematice 

formally announced the close of one long era of intellectual 
development, and the inauguration of a new philosophical era, 
in which the inquiring human intellect casts loose from certain 
fi xed moorings to which it had earlier been anchored. Hence- 
forth the thought of man must sail the open sea and find, 
instead of the old landmarks, stars by which to navigate its 
course. 

This prospect which is opened up by the Prmcipia Matbe- 
matica we shall discuss later. Here we take note only of the 
contribution of this work to logic. The authors show conclu- 
sively enough that the propositions of pure mathematics can be 
restated without loss of cogency in strictly Ic^cal terms. 
Mathematical theory becomes a compact but tremendous sym- 
bolic system, the purely logical character of which can be 
made explicit by a meticulous and rather tedious process of 
analysis and symbol definition. The forms and operations of 
thought, it follows, are not to be identified with the rudi- 
mentary code sanctified by traditional logic. They are at least 
as many, as various, as flexible, and as capable of development 
as are the operations and s\*mbolizations of a creative mathe- 
matical science. 

Russell undertook this inqui^ into logical form in the inter- 
ests of realistic philosophy. .Ir was, he assured the writer, ex- 
pressly to undercut and to discredit the assumptions of Kant 
concerning mathematics, that he proceeded to this laborious 



REALISM 


469 

that they are firmly adhered to. We can define meanings and 
symbols as we please, and uphold our definitions by fiat — ^for 
example, in a dictionary the authority of which we enforce. 
On the other hand, there are Sv-nthetic or descriptive proposi- 
tions which make statements about things and natural proc- 
esses; and these nrcposirinns. based upon cur limited perception 
and our partial understanding of nature, are subject to change. 
These prcrr;?;t:cns are less than absolute, being only probable 
in their truth. As Hume had shown, we have no absolute or 
certain knowledge of matters of fact. The absolute certainty 
of a proposition is sufficient evidence of its purely logical and 
nondescriptive character. 

Mathematical science, ever since the time of Pythagoras and 
Plato, had seemed to constitute a knowledge at once absolute 
and certain in its truth, and universally descriptive in its ap- 
plicability to nature; and the existence of this mathematical 
science had seemed to demtKistrate the pciscsi:>.r. by man of a 
rational faculty able to reach such absolute and universal 
knowledge of fact. The reduction of mathematical propositions 
10 symbolic definitions ended this long error, by sharply demar- 
cating the sphere of free or arbitrary logical construction from 
that of scientific hypothe^; and it thus ended, presumably for 
perpetuity, the era of rationalistic metaphysics. However, this 
clear demarcation of the fields of logic and science does not 
solve, but only makes more acute and definable, the problem of 
the relation between freely constructed symbolic s\-stcn:s, such 
as mathematical theory, and the descriptive theories of em- 
pirical science, within which mathematical theory is somehow 
incorporated. Does physical science, for example, with its in- 
timate dependence upon mathematical theory, endow this incor- 
porated logic with descriptive meaning and truth, and show the 
c:.ir_'::5r.surnb:l:r.' of pure logic with material fact? Or does 
our awareness of thK purely logical structure in physical 
science warn us that physical theory is a human construction, 
which may not be accepted as the sheer description of an 



REALISM 


471 

himself. The human individual lives as a member of society, in 
the polidcal government of which he necessarily participates; 
and his responsibility is not limited to an abstention from injury 
to othere. His political power, just insofar as it is exercised, 
makes him the guardian of others. Inevitably, he is his brother’s 
keeper. His right use of political power makes him the creator 
of other lives, his abuse of it makes him the destroyer of other 
lives. Moral and political responsibility therefore constituces a 
positive responsibility for others’ good; and our insight into 
what is good for others presupposes our interest in others and 
our love of them. An atomistic individualism, limiting individ- 
ual responsibility to a negative withholding of injury from 
others, will not indefinitely support democratic government. 
This requires the positive assamprion by each individual of the 
responsibilities of a governor of the social and moral com- 
munity, within which each life is determined and by which it 
is shaped. 

But we should be satisfied, perhaps, to leave to the future an 
estimate of this most important thinker of his gcncrarion, whose 
tremendous effect upon thought will be patent as long as intel- 
lectual curiosity impels the human mind. We will return to 
further consideration of Russell’s influence in our treatment of 
contemporary positivism. 

Alfred North Whitehead (bora 1861), Russell’s collaborator 
in the Principia MatheTnatica, proceeded from this same Ic^cal 
study to farreaching metaphysical speculations. It is interesting 
to observe how these two men were so differently influenced 
by that study, and to speculate on the reasons. Russell, trained 
in philosophy and favorable to the empirical British tradition, 
was con&med in his suspicion that logic is an empty or 
“trivial” knowledge, having to do chiefly with symbols and 
their ntanipulation. Whitehead, an able and creative mathe- 
matician, was confirmed in his belief that conceptual construc- 
tion is the heart or dynamo of thought itself, and was encour- 
aged to trust to his logical talent in an attack upon the largest 



REALISM 


473 

allows us, therefore, to infer the relationships among nonex- 
pcrienced events; and it is these we seek to define in theoretical 
knowledge. Such knowledge is abstract and indirect; but be- 
cause our intellectual cognition is itself an occasion, directly 
ingredient with our immediate perceptions and, through these, 
indirectly ingredient with external events, natural knowledge 
is incorporate with its object, the external world; and this is 
how the Cartesian dualism of mind and matter is overcome. 
We are hereby assured that experience and knowledge, al- 
though not to be identified with nature, are homogeneous with 
nature. Experience is the stuff of which nature is made; and 
nature is also the stuff of which experience is made. 

Whitehead’s ir.etaphysic is in many ways superior to its 
model, the Leibnizian monadism. It is extraordinarily versatile, 
flexible, competent in its interpretation of science. It is never 
without a philosophical answer; nor will the answer strain 
credulity although Whitehead’s terminology may tax the 
memory. Leibniz needed both a deus ex vmcbma to set the stage 
of nature, in God the Creator of the monads, and a deus in 
machina, in God the Supreme Monad. Whitehead, like Samuel 
Alexander, requires only a deity who works as an active and 
universal nrincinie of realization, moderating and informing the 
careers of those who freely cooperate. For Whitehead, individ- 
ual being is authentically free and indeterminate, and not 
predestined. Almost certainly, there never was so ingenious a 
metaphysical system as this of Whitehead; and not impossibly 
it may continue indefinitely to be just that — the laa meta- 
ph3^cal system to end metaphysical systems. 

Why has this brilliant speculative construction, so ingemoiB 
and plausible, which at so little cost saves so much — all the 
freedoms, all aesthetic qualities and moral values, the two 
criteria of science, and religion along with science — ^why has 
this genial philosophy elicited so little intellectual response, and 
not become the rallying point and credo of all honest and 
reverent intellectuals? Whitehead’s vocabulary is somewhat 



REALISM 


475 

certainly not the old rationalisn:. which identified its rational 
intuition of eternal essence with a theoretical knowledge of the 
cosmic process of nature. In Whitehead’s system, the essences 
provide only the atomic elements, out of which existent actual- 
ities are composed; and because the elements are infinite in 
number, they can compose into an infinite variety of existent 
worlds, so that the character of existent fact is contingent and 
must be discovered by observation. Whitehead’s conception is 
therefore consistent with empirical method; but does it illu- 
minate and justify, or does it on the contrary make inexplicable 
and dubious, an empirical theoretical science? In what sense is 
our science d«criptive of this world, if its theory would 
equally well apply to innumerable other worlds, variously 
compounded of the same essences? And how can we conceive 
of the relation between these two realms — the intuited realm 
of subsistent essence, and the experienced and lived world of 
particular existence? Does this sort of realism ignore the real 
problem, which is the relation of general knowledge to par- 
ticular existential fact? Does it know the creed and share the 
burden of a genuine empiricism, which intends to affirm the 
ultimacy and the intelligibility of individual being? Or docs it, 
like Plato, leave inexplicable the relation between the actual and 
the ideal, and lead us toward skepticism? 

Russell, although he too affirms the cognitive ultimacy of 
ultra-individual essences, such as are reached by an introspec- 
tive epistemological analysis, is no longer inclined to give them 
—etaphvsical status, but leaves their relationship to existential 
reality problematic. It is quesrionablc whether contemporary 
realism, in trying to save theoretical science from its critics by 
i nsistin g upon the identity with “reality” of the objects de- 
scribed by theoretical analysis, leaves science more securely 
established or more exposed to rationalistic distortion or 
skeptical dianissal. Presupposed in all philcsophical realism of 
this kind is the csscmpticn. conscious or implicit, that some sort 
of analysis other than scientific analysis is needed to establish 



nSALISM 


477 

hension of real objects. Cognititm, in this view, has a peculiar 
status, and may not be treated as a merely psychological process, 
integrally part of the context of natural processes which are the 
object of cognition. The objects of cognition. Meinong taught, 
may or may not exist — they must include, indeed, objects 
which cann t t sxist, as well as objects which do exist 

and objects -..i^ ■ : exist. Thought, in a word, is something 
distinct from, and more extensive than, the nature which is 
thought about. It is essential to thought that it should be able 
to contemplate and define certain “objective realities,” whether 
or not these “realities” exist. Meinong is led to affirm the being 
of a realm of subsistents, ue. of real and intelligiMy interrelated 
objects which transcend the realm of existent things. This 
“objective” realm of essences he finds to be the basis or sub- 
stance of all scientific and ethical theory. 

Edmund Husserl (bom 1859) has defended, elaborated, and 
applied a related conception in the studies known as Fhenome^ 
nology. This name would appear to derive from Hegel’s realistic 
study The Phenomenology of Mind, which claimed that an in- 
tellectual cognition of perceptual phenomena, or appearances, 
discerns those universal yet “concrete” forms which are the 
substance of ultimate reality. {The Real appears/) Husserl, 
however, distinguishes phenomenological cognition as a peculiar 
sort of act, neither merely perceprucl nor yet metaphysical in 
Hegel’s sense. For Hegel, cognition is rational and absolute be- 
cause it comprehends a particular phenomenon as an integral 
part of the universal and absolute whole, which alone is real 
being. For Husserl, the absolute rational cognition grasps only 
its present object — a view which does not involve metaphysical 
assumptions of a monistic sort. Phenomenology thus belongs to 
the new realism in its postulation of a vast plurr.!:ty of real 
objects, known directly and with absolute certaintx- by the 
mind. It differs from other forms of new realism in stressing 
that these objects arc real and objective only for a conscious 
subject. As its origins suggest, it is a realism which leans toward 



REALISM 


479 

Most -widely kno-wn of this realistic group, perhaps, is George 
Santayana (bom 1863), whose mellifluous style and literary 
skill give to his writings an appeal apparently irresistible to the 
reader untrained in philc-scphy. Santayana’s earliest realism was 
of a Platonic sort. In >J'j L;; ;? of Reason he invited the reader to 
the contemplative life, in the enjoyment of an interminable 
play with eternal essences mathematical, physical, and aesthetic. 
From this Platonic heaven Santayana seems to have fallen -with- 
out a parachute upon an earth inconsiderately hard and matcriaL 
We live, he -writes with infinitely cadenced complaint, tom 
between heaven and earth, and strung between the “life of 
reason” and a sordid “animal faith.” This is Santayana’s state- 
ment of the problem of the relation between the realistic 
essences which are open to rational cognition, and the empirical 
knowledge of existent fact which is obtained by -way of ob^rva- 
tion and probable hypothesis. The problem itself he never 
dirccdy attacks; but he unceasingly bewails it, in a poetic prose 
which charms, perhaps because it lulls, the philosophical 
neophyte. 

A sturdier representative of American realism is Jobn Elof 
Boodm (bora i860). Boodin’s empirical or “functional” real- 
ism consistently avoids iKaj duali^ of essence and existence 
which remains the insolubje jresidue of more strictly realistic 
theories of knowledge. B<iodin’s primary business with epis- 
temology, it might not unfairly 5^ gaid^ j-© get rid of it -with 
its apparent hasolublc^ in ^rdcr to advance from the latest find- 
ings of the sped;?! sdencfe to more comprehensive and unified 
speculation abou^ the w^rld. His “functional realism” sets the 
mind in material -^terattion with its bodily setting and -with 
the external cnvironm^lt, the result being that natural knowl- 
ed^ remains functionally corporate with its object nature, yet 
specifically distinct from it. This conception of functional rela- 
tionship is further developed in a mct'.physics of organization. 
The many individual and o^-erlapping energy-systems W'hich 
comprise reality reveal an unstable yet enduring hierarchical 



REAUSM 


481 

structures defined by theoretical science to be intuited by the 
pure reason, the sensory perception of particular fact serving 
only to illustrate, not to discover, these real structures. Modem 
science, nominalistically influenced, has emphasized the role of 
perceived particular fact, which it allows to be the criterion of 
theoretical truth and the whole source of theoretical knowl- 
edge. The Cartesian philosophy, in its defense of theoretical 
science, renounced the dualism of matter and form which had 
made Greek realism intelligible; but it affirmed the realistic 
creed more emphatically than ever, by identifying the concrete 
being of nature with the structure defined by geometrical 
theory. This Cartesian realism failed, we saw, to explain the 
facts of time, motion, and particularity', which were earlier 
taken care of by the Greek concept of matter; and the em- 
pirical attack seemed in the eighteenth century to have dis- 
credited all realism. Then came the bold attempt of the post- 
Kantians to save realism by attributing realistic truth not to 
observant empirical theory, but to a “reflective” philosophical 
theory. These men were quite serious in their denial of cogency 
to empirical science, and in their excogitation of a new “philos- 
ophical science.” It soon became evident to other serious men, 
however, that this return to realistic faith at the price of aban- 
doning empirical science saved only the form and not the sub- 
stance of that faith. Either the results of theoretical science had 
to be surreptitiously reestablished by the theoretical philos- 
opher, or Ws “philosophical science” lacked ail cogency and 
even meanmg. And so we are brought to contemporary r^ism, 
which is a fresh effort to establish the cogency of theoretical 
science, by affirming again and in some new way the identity 
with ultimate reality of the objects defined by science. 

How far does this latest effort succeed? Contemporary real- 
ism usually admits that the special theories of science are 
reached by hytpothescs based upon a study of particular faa. 
The realist is empirical in his admission that the descriptive 
theories of science are only probable hypotheses. We have no 



SEAtISM 


483 

intellectual faith. Realism affirms the power of thought, and 
calls upon us to accept as truly descriptive of nature the con- 
clusions of an intellectual study of nature. The reality which 
science aims to describe, however, is existent nature; and the 
reality which realism finally establishes is that of subsistent 
being, a realm of essence the relation of which to existence re- 
mains mysterious and ircxplrciblc. We will suggest later that 
all realism, old or new, fails to grasp the chief motive of em- 
pirical thought, and does less than justice to the empirical 
science of today. The realism of science is something else than 
this philosophic.:! realism. 

Modern science rejected Greek and scholastic realism, we may 
say, because it was necessar}' to reject the finality of all merely 
general and theoretical kr.ovdcdgc. in order to allow the con- 
tinuous progress of theoretical science in the light of new' 
evidence. The concept of scientific progress, we shall find, re- 
quires an advance to a new and larger conception of scientific 
truth. But this advance cannot renounce that faith in the 
descriptive power of science which realism seeks to uphold. 
The philosophy of the future must be an enlarged realism. We 
may not, in order to do justice to particular fact and crrpirica! 
science, renounce our faith in the descriptive truth of knowl- 
edge; yet this is what the philosophies of prcgtr.at;s~ and 
positivism, to which we now turn, w'ould seem to require. 

Notes for Further Reading 

1. Moore, G. E., Philosophical Studies. New York, Harcourt, 

Brace and CcT:pc-:r. 1922. 

2. Ethics. New York, Henry Holt and Company, 191Z. 

3. Russell, B., P!::lc,iopb:j.z! Essays. London, Longmans, Green 

and Cempeny, 19 10. 

4. The Problems of Philosophy. New York, Henry Holt 

and Companv. rpiz. 

5. MystL'U’u and Logic. Boston, Longmans, Green and 

Company. 1918. 

<5. An Analysis of .Mind. New Y'ork, The Macmillan Com- 





24 PRAGMATISM 


CONTEMPORARY REALISM IS THE CHARACTER- 

isdc oudook in British philosophical circles, so prag- 
matism has had its center and widest fcilowing in the United 
States of America, There have been pragmatic thinkers in 
Britain and Europe; but only in this country has pragmarism 
been a movement or school effectively propagating a common 
outlook and faith. And pragmatism remains, in spite of its occa- 
sional appearance elsewhere, a philosophical movement largely 
identified with America, 

It was only in the twentieth century that American thought 
attempted to find for itself a distinctive vocabulary and for- 
mulation. Colonial America had preserved a motley of theolog- 
ical. philosophical and moral creeds brought from Europe, 
England and Scotland. It w'as to follow these 
creeds without hindrance that many American colonists had 
crossed the Atlantic and settled in the New World. Calvinistic 
and Lutheran theology, Puritan zeal, the political philosophy 
of John Locke, and the “common-sense realism” cultivated in 
the Scottish universities had satisfied a colonial society which 
was not so much indifferent to philosophies! ideas (indeed, it 
W'as somewhat u.nu.sus;ly committed to them) as absorbed by 
the practical busmess of creating out of great material resource 



PRAGMATISM 


487 

formalized. To what degree American scholarship will retain 
these German borrowings remains to be seen. Along with Ger- 
man pedantry came a good deal of German philosophy, usually 
that of the post-Kantian idealists; and for a time it seemed as if 
German transcendentalism might take root on American soil. 
Its ablest exponent was Josiah Royce, a son of California 
pioneers, and long the colleague of William James at Harvard 
University. Royce was a very independent disciple of his Ger- 
man teachers. He never confused the Absolute with human 
experience; and he remained very empirical in his emphasis on 
individual being, and in his refusal to transcend temporal and 
spatial relations. Where the German absolutists tended to see 
the supreme actualization of the Absolute Mind in the political 
state, Royce found it m the religious community of mankind. 
In such ways, he eliminated those aspects of German absolutism 
which made it least acceptable to the American public; but he 
was nevertheless to witness the realistic and pragmatic reaction 
which virtually swept absolute idealism from the lecture halls 
of America. 

The leader of this reaction was William James (1842-1910). 
James came to philosophy late, by way of art, medicine, and 
psychology. To this training he owed his most fruitful concep- 
tions; but it may have prevented him from 2pprcc;r.t:ng the his- 
torical development of philosophy, s.-£ its t.; certain 

root problems apart frc~ v- hich it loses its importance and 
even its identity. James’ study of psychology, a new and ad- 
venturous discipline still in search of a “method,” quickened 
his perception of the empirical and experimental character of 
science, and made him impatient with every sort of formalism; 
and these tendencies were strengthened by what he found in 
his study of psychical processes. In his Principles of Psychol- 
ogy, a work no longer authoritative but still the most stimulat- 
ing of psychological texts, James moved from the introspective 
associational psychology which had been current since Hume 
to a functional and biological analysis of behavior. He refused 



PRAGMATISM 


489 

changing process which integrates the organism into its en- 
vironment. In man, this process happens to be conscious and 
inteHigent; but consciousness is not something additive to the 
process. “Consciousness as such” does not exist. Concepts are 
only fixities or uniformities of interaction, appearing in this 
vital process of adjustment. They are only relative constants, 
subject to change. It is because we rigidly and artificially 
separate this vital process into two incommensurable parts, a 
substantial world and a substantial mind, that there arise the 
insoluble pseudo-problems of which rtct'inhy'f'c:;! theories arc 
the pretended solution. If our knowledge of the world is our 
functional adjustment to the world, kr.ov. Iedge is conditioned 
both by what lies outside of us and by what transpires within 
us. If this is so, we cannot suppose that knowledge defines a 
reality wholly independent of ourselves, a thing-in-itself which 
needs only to be realistically inspected and described. Nor, 
on the other hand, should we conclude that knowledge is there- 
fore wholly nondescriptive and subjective. The cognitive 
process is real enough, wherever it proceeds and whatever it 
be; and it involves both external nature and human activity in 
its content and structure. 

James rightly believed that this functional ccrrcccrior.. which 
sees in cognition an adjustment or relation between man and his 
environment, requires a new conception of what constitutes 
truth. Earlier philosophy had never wholly renounced the 
familiar assumption that knowledge is true insofar as it de- 
scribes a structure which is intrinsic to nature itself, and inde- 
pendent of the mind. The philosopher might realistically 
affirm the identity of the -object with ultimate reality; 

or he might claim only that a certain correspondence exists be- 
tween what is cognized and what is real, much as a photogreph 
represents the thing photographed; or, failing to demonstrate 
even such correspondence, he might lapse into skepticism. But 
James struck a new and bold course. If cegnition is man’s 
adjustment to his environment, he said, then true knowledge is 



PRAGMATISM 


491 

cion of the earlier empiricism, American pragmatism is 
primarily a critical doctrine, antagonistic to rationalistic meta- 
physics. Its power and its purpose are never apparent to the 
thinker who fails to appreciate this fact, and who demands 
from pragmatism a systematic doctrine. The pragmatism of 
James was his criticism of European rationalism. 

The pragmatism of Dewey and his followers extends this 
criticism to certain current forms of realism, which are showm, 
the writer believes correctly, to involve rationalistic implica- 
tions. And if American perperaates the empirical 

opposition to absolutistic philosophy, it is also the expression 
of a liberal faith which continually opposes absolutism in prac- 
tical life. Institutions, it teaches, are made by man for man; and 
they are therefore subject to perpetual criticism and contin- 
uous modification by those who use them. 

In America pragmatism gives new voice and fresh applica- 
tion to the moral and intellectual faith which has 
modem science and modern society. It is the philosophy of the 
liberal and progressive thmker; and it claims to have found a 
more just and effective statement of the moral and philo- 
sophical truth which inspires modem man. But although prag- 
matism preserves a tradition carried from its parental source 
some centuries ago, and only now given new and forceful 
expression, the pragmatist is not oblivious of what has tran- 
spired smee then; and he is especially aware of the philosophical 
significance of evolutionary science. It might almost be said 
that pragmatism is a form of empirical philosophy which 
identifies science wdth evolutionary biology, whereas earlier 
empiricism had identified science with physical and chemical 
theory. This and other shifts of approach appropriate to con- 
temporary thought make pragmatism a doctrine difficult to 
define; and this difficulty is increased by the critical or negative 
character of the doctrine, which leaves its positive affirmations 
fluid and elusive. 

James’ initial statement of the doctrine, that trath is the cash- 



PRAGMATISM 


493 

dition of the city’s becoming free of smoke; and nere, belief 
may help to create its own evidence. Bat does our belief that 
the moon causes the tides help to make this belief come true? 
Or is this belief true simply because it states a fact which is 
wholly independent of whether the fact helps us or hurts us, 
and of whether it is believed or not? Can we, where King 
Canute could not, retard the tide by refusing to acknowledge 
its advance? James’ pragmatism seemed to collide with every 
sort of realism — not only with philosophical realism, but widi 
the realism of science and common sense. 

The defense and development of pragmatism was under- 
taken by John Dewey (bom 1859), w’ho has remained its most 
fluent and influential advocate. Dewey brought to this crusade 
arguments and conceptions derived from nineteenth-century 
European philosophy, especially from the post-Kantians. Like 
James, he was influenced in his approach to philosophy by his 
study of psychological and biological facts. He placed knowl- 
edge in its concrete matrix, the progress of individual and social 
life; and he viewed it as an instrument of ad'-ostmenr, serving 
the organism and society by bringing each into adjustment 
with the other, and also into adjustment with nature at large. 
But Dewey was also early and profoundly influenced by ^ 
thought of Hegel, which determined his epistemolc^ and hs 
philosophical method; and if we would understand conten^io- 
rary pragmatism, which is that of Dewey, we must appreciate 
its relation to the Hegelian metaphysic. in spite of the fact that 
few pragmatists seem to be aware of this influence and that 
Dewey himself has forgotten it. 

How could the Hegelian system, which we saw to be the 
most absolute of rationalisms, be converted into a doctrine 
which is extremely empirical, and critical of every sort of 
rationalism? Hegel, we remember, had created what he called a 
“new logic,” namely “dialectical logic.” Ordinary logic, he 
said, is purely abstract, trivial, and nondescriptive — ^its defini- 
tions are merely nominal or verbal; but there is a “concrete 



PRAGMATISM 


495 

The actuality he sees is the process of knowledge itself, in- 
tegrating mind and nature. This process does, of course, absorb 
and digest the new facts which continuously come into the 
mind; but this involves for Dewey no realistic conception of an 
actuality external to the mind, and independent of it. The new 
facts which enter the mind are not to be conceived as existmg 
in their own right, because they derive their character as 
“facts” wholly from their relationship to old and new hypoth- 
eris. Dewey’s pragmatism, in short, is a new and empirical 
version of the post-Kantian idealism. It seems to attribute 
reality or actuality only to the process and content of mind- 
It avoids any realistic discussion of the relation of knowledge 
to an external world, a reality which is not knowledge but the 
object-which-knowledge-describes. It allows us to discuss only 
old-facts-as-known, hypothesis or knowledge, and new-facts- 
as-knowoi. It confines us within human experience. 

It should be perceived that the idea of a “concrete logic” 
necessarily involves an idealistic metaphysics. Logic is truly the 
study of explicit knowledge, wherein logic di^guishcs the 
most general form from the varying content. If logical forms 
are “concrete,” in the sense that they still contain all their 
particular factual content, then we cannot hope to distinguish 
what is general knowledge of nature from what is particular 
fact, nor from whatever it is that appears to the mind as par- 
ticular occurrence. We cannot distinguish mind from nature. 
But pragmatism seldom acknowledges its idealistic presupposi- 
tions. It obscures these by its definitioa of knowledge and 
intelligence, which it identifies with the organic process of ad- 
justment to environment. This definition itself implies, of 
course, a realistic and nonidcalistic conception of nature, since 
it separates the organism from its environment. But the bodily 
organism, it is then said, is itself just the process of intelligent 
readjustment. The body is its life, and the life is its intelligence. 
This implicit idealism is further obscured by the pragmstist’s 
dominating concern with the social environment. The most 



PRAGMATISM 


497 

of man, is in radical evolurion, and submits to no fixities of 
statement. Even if we were to conceive of a fixed physical en- 
vironment conditioning man, knowledge would still be fluid 
r.7d Trr--:??:-,". never definitive; for each intelligent readjust- 
: t>.; c..-ganism to that freed environment would con- 
stitute a change of organic character, this w'ould establish a 
changed relationship of organism to environment, and this 
would generate new facts reruiring new the-.' is. In Hegel, 

we saw, the conception of natural evolution was degraded into 
that of a fixed dialectical system. By Dewey, evolution is given 
its rightful character; but Dewey still, like Hegel, presents the 
evolution idealistically, as that of intelligence or concrete mind. 
The needed readjustment of a thing to its environment is de- 
scribed as constituting a “problem”; the thing’s reactions to the 
problematic simation are a trial and effort applying implicit 
or explicit hypotheses, which apprehend the character of the 
situation in its relation to the thing; and the true hypothesis is 
that which effects the readjustment, producing satisfaction. 
The satisfaction is only temporary, because the new' readjust- 
ment will sooner or later generate new problems. 

Pragmatism originated, we saw, in the pragmaric definition 
of truth. The truth of a proposition was said to be its beneficent 
consequence, or the character of the prcpcsitinn which condi- 
tions this beneficent consequence. The truth of a belief is the 
good it does. To say this is to subordinate all factual judgment 
to moral judgment. This is the great virtue and appeal of prag- 
matism, that it converts all factual and scientific truth into 
moral truth. Kant had been compelled to distinguish scientific 
knowledge, as only phenomenal, from the true insight which 
is conscience. The post-Kantians had attempted to convert this 
moral intuition into a systematic philosophy, transcending a 
merely descriptive science. Dewey, rejecting the rationalistic 
presuppositions of Kantian thought, flatly identifies moral 
intuition with scientific intelligence. If science speaks truth, 
then its affirmations are those which effect beneficent conse- 



PRAGMATISM 


499 

is defined as being progressive and creative. More specificaHr, 
Dewey has convinced the jurist that law is but the instrument, 
continuously renovated, by which society readjusts itself to 
changing economic and intellectual conditions, so that law 
exists to serve life and not to control it; and jurists have turned 
to an empirical and nragmatic He has told the 

statesman and citizen that governmental institutions may not 
be more fixated than the social actualities w'hich generate and 
use government; and pragmatism becomes the faith of the 
political radical. In pedagogy, the educator is w^amed against 
formal disciplines, and inspired to a “progressive education” 
which will develop the native powers of the pupil, by exercis- 
ing them in ways preparing him for the actualities of con- 
temporary life. By a pragmatic criticism of art, the artist is 
weaned from classicism and the pursuit of art for art’s sake, 
and led to make his craftsmanship the instrument of social re- 
form and the dignifier of human labor and the common life. 
In matters religious, the believer is direaed toward a liberal 
modernism which makes little of formal creed and institutional 
tradition, deprecates sectarian differences, and translates theo- 
logical metaphysics into ethical doctrine and sociological in- 
struction. “Science” and “society" become terms quick by 
one another into new significance; and “Science and Society” 
becomes the slogan of a reformatory program which will re- 
create every human activity, not least by bringing the too 
specialized departments and institutions of human life into 
reciprocal stimulation and readjustment, in the acknowledg- 
ment of a common social responsibility. 

All of this is high achievement; and surely no empiricist, nor 
any liberal, moral, and progressive thinker, would desire to 
diminish or undo the stiraulatmg influence wdiich prag 'utisrr: 
has exerted and will continue to e.xert upon American society. 
Pragmatism is a complex, rich, and ir.ar.y-sf'i;d doctrine. It 
revives and empowers the largest and most liberal tradition of 
modernity, going back to the earlier sources of this tradidon. 



PRAGMATISM 


501 

that knowledge should be instrumental, and that we should 
perceive and establish its instrumentality, we most have descrip- 
tive knowledge of a real world, made up of existent persons 
and things. 

If pragmatism has meaning only for one who is at heart a 
realist, what does pragmatism add to the realistic theory of 
knowledge? Our actual knowledge at any moment comprises 
a comprehensive summary of observed past occurrence. Prag- 
matism reminds us that this knowledge is not final nor absolute, 
but may be modified by future experience. We use our present 
knowledge when we hazard predictions, and the observation 
of the predicted occurrence confirms the knowledge on which 
the prediction was based. The pragmatist comes to regard this 
future confirmation of present knowledge as the sole verifica- 
tion of knowledge. The truth of the hypothesis, he says, lies 
wholly in its relation to the future occurrence which verifies 
it, i.e., makes it come true. But, in sober fact, the truth of any 
actual hypothesis lies wholly in its relation to past and present 
fact, and to no degree in its relation to future fact. It is past 
occurrence, so far as known, which establishes an hypothesis; 
and the future occurrence which may confirm the hypothesis 
cannot do this until it too has occurred, and is past. Further, 
the prediction which later confirms an hypothesis need not be 
and usually is not some practical application of the hypothesis. 
It may be a purely scientific prediction, concerned only to test 
scientific truth. Knowledge is not made true by being used. 
Its descriptive truth lies in its comprehension of observed par- 
ticular fact; and its instrumental value derives from its descrip- 
tive truth. 

In its conception of truth, pragmatism still does unconscious 
service to the idol of absolute knowledge, a service w’hich 
finally leads to skepticism. If the truth of a theory lay in its 
future consequence, knowledge would never be possessed, it 
would always be only anticipated. The pragmatist is led to 
identify knowledge with verified particular prediction because 



PRAGMATISM 


503 

and because it has quickened moral ideals nurtured by centuries 
of moral and religious education. Already, however, pragma- 
tism begins to reveal its inherent inadequacies. It begins to infect 
the scientist with skepticism, by destroying his faith in the 
descriptive power of theory, and by persuading him that his 
theories are merely mental constructs implemental to predic- 
tion. And it begins to foster an unhealthy jurisprudence, willing 
to overlook the absolute and eternal requirements of justice, 
and to question the constitutional securements of justice, in too 
plastic an accommodation of legal principles to local and 
transient pressures. In Europe, pragmatism has been the re- 
source of violent and reactionary groups, who defend their 
unscrupulous and tyrannical programs of action on the ground 
that the success of these programs, that is to say their forceful 
actualization, will pragmatically justify them. Pragmatism was 
the activisme of the reactionaries who betrayed France, and 
of the chauvinists who marched on Rome. “Just think this new 
Rome,” cried Mussolini, “believe in it, and the thought will be 
made fact and verify itself!” 

There is one other argument for pragmatism, however, which 
should not be overlooked. We have concluded that the only 
criteria of truth are logic and observed fact, which is to ex- 
clude the pragmatic criterion of practical utility. In striemess, 
the criteria of logic and observed fact do not suffice to single 
out just one hypothesis as true, invalidating all others. The 
same body of factual evidence will always support a oluralir.’- 
of self-consistent theories; and the ground upon which we 
prefer one of these alternative thories is in fact some pragmatic 
consideration of convenience, familiarity, or simplicity. Thus 
there is and will always remain a pragmatic element in knowl- 
edge. But is this an argument for or against the descriptive 
cogency of knowledge? We can use it in several ways. We can 
argue that science is never quite descriptive, since it involves 
some consideration of human convenience. We can say that the 
alternative theories are descriptively equivalent, since they 



I^RAGMATISM 505 

12, Dewey, J*, Democracy and Education. New York, Tte Mac- 
millan Company, 1916, - 

I j, The Quest for Certainty. New York, Minton Balch find 

Company, 1929, 

Reconstruction in Philosophy. New York, Henry Holt 

and Company, 1920. 

ij, Experience and Nature. La Salle, III, The Open Court 

Publishing Company. 1925. 

1 5, Liberalism and Social Action. New York, G, P. Put- 

nam’s Sons, 1935. 

17. Logic, the Theory of Inquiry. New York, Henry Holt 

and Company, 1938. 

18. Dewey, J., and Tufts, J. H., Ethics. New York, Henry Holt 

and Company, 1908. 

19. Dewey, J., and others. Creative Intelligence. New York, Henry 

Holt and Company, 1917. 

20. Ratner, E. ed.. The Philosophy of Devcey. New York, Henry 

Holt and Company, 1928. Selections. 

21. Moore, A. W., Pragmatism and Its Critics. Chicago, University 

of Chicago Press, ipio. 

22. Mead, G. H., The PhUoscphy of the Act. Chicago, University 

of Chicago Press, 1938. 

23. Otto, M. C., The Human Enterprise. New York, F. S. Crofts 

and Company, 1940. 

24. Laird, J., Recent Philosophy. London, Thornton Butterworth, 

Ltd., 1936, 



POSITIVISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENC3E 


507 

this side of ultimate reality. But the term “positivism” was 
chiefly propagated by nineteenth-century Auguste Comte. 
Comte agreed with Kant that science is the sole authentic 
knowledge, and that it is still only phenomenal; but he refused 
to appeal beyond science, as did Kant, to a faculty of moral 
cognition able to grasp noumenal being, t.e. reality itself. Comte 
wished to revive the rationalistic faith of the eighteenth-cen- 
tury Enlightenment; but he was sufliciently influenced by the 
empirical criticism of Hume and Kant to be desirous of avoid- 
ing metaphysics. His proposal was to moderate the claim of 
science, by allowing that empirical or natural know'leii^ 
reaches conclusions which are less than absolute, and which 
describe only the phenomenal realm accessible to direct per- 
ception; yet at the same time he wished to establish science as 
the sole reliable cognition accessible to man. This estimate of 
science he called “positivism,” intending to distinguish scien- 
tific method, as the sole approach to positive and verifiable 
knowledge, from the methods used by the theologan and the 
metaphysician. As Touchstone modestly said of Audrey, “A 
poor virgin, sir, an ill-favored thing, sir, but mine own,” so the 
positivist deprecates any claim to realistic knowledge, yet 
ascribes exclusively to natural science whatever knowledge man 
may possess. 

TTus positivistic outlook persisted tliroughout the nineteenth 
century, being especially favored among scientists and those 
close to science. In Germany, shortly after the mid-century, 
it was given a new formulation. Albert Lange used positivism 
as his basis for an attack upon materialistic metaphysics. Ac- 
cepting as his initial postulate the critical positivism of Kant, 
Lange proceeded to show that materialism violates Kant’s pro- 
hibition of dogmatic metaphysics, in that it carries the categories 
of science beyond human experience into pure spcc-alation; 
but he then diverged from Kant in his naturalistic account of 
the origin of the categories. For Kant, these categories were 
fixed forms of thought, transcending the variable content of 



POSITIVISM AND THE PHItOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 


509 

these physical entities as existing in another psychical realm, 
not that of the physical entities themselves; and so we proceed 
to an absolute dualism of mind and matter, with its insoluble 
problems. But in fact, Mach meant, we know directly only 
one sort of entities, namely immediate sensations with their 
interrelations; and both “physical” and “psychical” facts belong 
in this one realm. 

We need not appeal, therefore, to an external reality lying 
beyond the realm of experience, and other than it. Our usual 
supposition, which is that we explain phenomena by showing 
them to be the effects of real things lying back of phenomena, 
is quite unnecessary, and presumably fdse. We are justified 
in believing only what is actually observed and attested by 
science — all further belief is gratuitous and “metaphysical.” 
We need to postulate, therefore, only the phenomenal realm. 

Mach also pointed out that definitions of scientific objects 
are conditioned by the experimental procedures pursued in 
their study. He recognized three criteria of scientific truth. 
First, we should accept as true only those relational complexes, 
i.e. theories, which can be reduced to sensational elements. 
Second, we should require logical consistency, even though 
this requires theoretical constructions going beyond what is 
strictly verifiable in experience. And third, our hypotheses 
should attain a maximum simplicity, economy, and utility as 
the agencies of precise description and accurate prediction. In 
these three requirements, Mach recognized the three aspects of 
cegnitien which have variously led to realism, idcali^ and 
pragmatism; but because he balances each aspect against die 
others, preferring none, he identifies himself with no one of 
these views. 

Similarly complex and inclusive is the positivism of other 
late nineteenth-century thinkers. The most notable and bril- 
liant of these was Henri Poincare (1854-1912), the leadmg 
mathematician of his time. The logical element in knowledge 
is found by Poincare to arise in mathematical intuition, w’hich 



posrrmsM and the philosophy of science 511 

and host of knowledge, and the legitimate seat of intellectual 
and political authority. The moral sense of the individual, felt 
as obligation to God or mankind or moral law, is really a sub- 
conscious awareness of society, induced by the pervasive force 
which is exerted by society upon individual thought and con- 
duct. Sociology is the smdy of this ultimate, real, and authorita- 
tive being which is society. Religion, law, moral theory, art, 
economic theory and practice, science, and even logic are all, 
according to this ’’^sociologisme" only the instruments and ex- 
pressions of the “collective mind.” 

This doctrine looks back by way of Comte’s sociology to 
Rousseau’s doctrine of the general will. In the writer’s opinion, 
it is one of the more perverse and dangerous fallacies of our 
tine. The “collective mind” can be used to justify extreme 
nationalism, racialism, or other immoral and antisocial preju- 
dice. In the name of science, this collectivism denies the ob- 
jectivity of scientific truth, and teaches that every society must 
have its peculiar science rooted in a peculiar logic. As the fount 
of morality, it would erect the collectivistic state, exercising an 
absolute authority which is implicitly accepted, it says, even 
in the individuars deepest sense of moral obligation. In the 
name of religion, it denies the objective truth of religion, and 
makes religious faith only conformity to collective opinion, or 
loyalty to one’s tribe. A similar doctrine, pursued by the Ger- 
man exponents of Kultur-philosaphie, encouraged the move- 
ment to Nazism. Nowhere is the moral confusion of European 
society so evident and so disastrous as in this pseudoscientific 
sociologism. 

Yet we have to recognize that this aberrance of thought, 
with its deification of society and convention, is a groping 
effort to do justice to the moral basis of knowledge, which 
is not to be so unhappily identified with “convention.” It is 
this moral basis which gives to science its universality, and 
prevents it from becoming protnucial, racial, national, and 
“sociological.” It is this moral basis, we shall see, which 



POSITIVISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 513 

of the symbols as these are defined by his manual, he finds that 
the two sides of the identity are only different ways of saying 
the same thing. Thus the identity is an analytic proposition be- 
cause it only reveals, upon analysis, the meanings of the sym- 
bols as defined; it is a tautological or self-evident proposition 
because it follows of necessity from the definitions of the 
symbols used. 

To show that mathematical theory can be reduced to logical 
theory, i.e. .to definitions of symbols together with the results 
of logical cpent:~r.s upon the definitions, was to show that 
mathematicd theory is not a descriptive science making state- 
ments about the structures and processes of nature. Mathemati- 
cal systems can be constructed ad libitwn, and they may be 
of any sort we please. If we do not like irrational numbers, 
we may construct a theory in which these will not occur. If 
we are not satisfied with the three dimensions of height, breadth, 
and depth, we may construct a geometry with four or forty 
dimensions. Thus the apparent necessity or certainty of mathe- 
matical propositions (two and two must be four, cannot be 
five) stems initially from our fidelity to the meanings we have 
allotted to symbols. “Two” means “one and one”; so “two and 
two” means “one and one and one and one”; but “one and 
one and one and one” means “four.” If we had criginclly de- 
fined “one and one and one and one” to be “five,” then “two 
and two” would be “five,” and “two and two are four” would 
be nonsense. 

Because Kant had based his whole conception of science 
upon the mistaken premise that mathematical prepositions are 
at once necessary and descriptive, the Principia Mathematica 
did in fact undermine and explode both the Kantian philoropV’ 
itself, and the metaphysical absolutisms which dspir.n.-;: 
upon it. But to dettiolish the Kantian philosophy avas not to 
remove the’ indubitable fact 'which Kant’s philosophy had en- 
deavored to explain. This indubitable fact is the theoretical or 
systematic character of scientific knowledge. Science proceeds 



JPOSmviSM AND THE PHIUBOPHY OF SCIENCE 515 

positivistic in tendency. But this positivistic stage seems already 
to be approaching its close. 

The categories of science which support the superstructure 
of natural knowledge, said Kant, arise from and express the 
mind’s essential function, which is to integrate human ex- 
perience. We cannot, accordingly, simply attribute to external 
reality itself the structures defined by these categories. If the 
structures initially express a unity which is imposed by the 
mind upon experience, they nee ’ not define a unity in external 
reality. There is good reason, Kant said, to deny to the cate- 
gories this external reference; because if we assume them to 
possess it, we are led to antinomies or self-contradictions. To- 
day, the function which Kant ascribed to the categories is 
seen to be fulfilled by the faculty of logical improviscdors, 
which generates symbolic systems such as mathematics; but 
because these logical systems are made at our pleasure, without 
resort to empirlcd verification, there seems to be no reason 
why they should describe anything external to ourselves; and 
when we do impute to them such descriptive cogency, we are 
led to nonsensical or meaningless statements which parallel the 
antinomies of pure reason discovered by Kant. This is the 
argument of the logical posimist; and it is not mistaken to see 
in it a modernized and corrected form of the Kantian criticism 
of absolutistic metapfipics. 

Like Kant, however, the logical positivist entertains a lively 
sense of the importance, the inescapability, and the self-in- 
tegrity of this logical structure in knowledge, in spite of the 
difficulties which it may raise with respect to our faith in 
thoretical description. Only where experience is so integrated 
into theoretical unity, the positivist says, do we have authentic 
knowledge. The ideal or objective of science, accordingly, is 
a theoretical system which would include all experience, at 
least insofar as this is theoretically conceivable. To this ideal of 
a “unity of science” the logical positivist calls all intelligent 
and well-meaning men. All scientists, all scholars, all educated 



JPOSmVISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 5x7 

Or shall we insist that the logical element, because it is integral 
with the theoretical descripti'^n. is part of the factual knowl- 
edge, and therefore invested with descriptive meaning? Is 
logic, as Kant would have inquired, at once self-evident and 
descriptive? 

On this issue, the three dominant philosophical traditions 
again make themselves felt and arouse controversial debate. 
The realist argues for the descriptive cogency of logic, and 
affirms its power to define an objective and real structure in 
the world. He may assert that the separation of logic from the 
descriptive material of science can never be quite complete;, so 
that logical theory remains a widest and most abstract descrip- 
tive knowledge. The pragmatist takes a middle position. The 
logical theory, he says, is the agency or instrument used in 
problem-solutions, just as is all scientific theory; and it will 
develop and shape itself as conditioned by the matrk of con- 
crete knowledge. Logic is therefore neither extraneous to the 
material facts, nor itself a statement of material fact; but it 
summarizes operations of analysis by means of which problems 
are solved. The positivist, at the other extreme position, holds 
that logical structure is separable and has been separated, and 
that its independence of the factual material to which it is 
applied, and within which it is incorporated to produce “knowl- 
edge,” constitutes a very real problem, which realism and 
pragmatism do not take sufficiently seriously. Contemporary 
positivism, in short — and this is its great merit — ^insists upon a 
fresh and thorcugkgoing examination of the relationslup of 
the rational element to the empirical element in knowledge; 
and it insists that this examination must start from the new 
grasp of logical form achieved in our own time. 

This inquiry was advanced by a group of men sometimes 
known as the “Vienna circle.” (xMach spent his later years in 
Vienna.) In his Tractatus logico-philosopldczis, Wittgenstein 
pointed to certain dif ficulties which would seem to prohibit 
a realistic theory of knowledge. Every system of logic, he con- 



POSITIVISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 


5*9 

the scene of a crime, might do service here. But it is evident that 
even the barest description of empirical fact must contain not 
only logical structure, but a good deal of everyday opinion or 
scientific hypothesis. There is no direct way of stating what is 
left in natural knowledge, when all theoretical form is taken 
away. The logical form and the empirical content of knowl- 
edge are not simply glued together, it is evident, in natural 
knowledge. It is upon the false supposition that the two ele- 
ments are so simply related that logical positivism breaks down. 

Already, however, the thinkers in this group arc attempting 
new approaches to the problem of the relationship of logic to 
fact. Any scientific or other description of faa (or, for that 
matter, any fantasy) is the rendition into communicable lan- 
guage of something which is not language. We may, therefore, 
study language itself, and especially scientific language, as a 
sort of medium in which Imowledge occurs. Much as the 
geometry of space enters into every material configuration 
existing in space, so the pattern of language will enter into 
every verbal description. We may turn, therefore, to a study 
of language-pattern, and discover in this way the linguistic 
structure which is incorporated in all explicit knowledge. This 
structure can be isolated, and reveals itself to be constituted 
of several elements. First, there is syntax, of which we learn 
something at school in our study of grammar. But school gram- 
mar is peculiar to one language, and we need a universal 
grammar. We possess this in the highly developed grammar 
or syntax of scientific language. The propositions which make 
up syntax consist wholly of statements about symbols and 
their relations. They refer to nothing outside of language. 
Thus a syntactical system can be elaborated which Im no 
meaning in the ordinary sense, because it refers to nothing out- 
side of itself; yet it is precisely definable and completely in- 
telligible. All pure mathematics, e.g. algebra, is such syntax. 
Syntactical systems can be given descriptive meanings by a 
process of interpretation. We first elaborate a purely algebmic 



POSITIVISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 52 1 

It constitutes really a new and corrected rarionalism. It agrees 
with the empiricist that logical study only abstracts the formal 
structure of empirical yet it also agrees with the 

realist and rationalist, who holds that logical or rational form 
constitutes something which regulates and conditions knowl- 
edge, and which is not to be identified with the empirical con- 
tent of knowledge. This movement raises again, in short, the 
issue which has long divided thinkers into the opposed camps 
of rationalism and empiricism: and it does this with the inten- 
tion and the promise of reconciling their differences. 

As yet, the proponents of this new and empirical rationalism 
are still somewhat uncertain of their way. They are embarrassed 
by their antecedent tradition, namely the nineteenth-century 
positivism which stoutly rejected all final “metaphysical” state- 
ment. They do not see that their clarification of the nature 
and function of logic may rid metaphysics of its terrors, by 
leaving wholly free and unconditioned the progress of em- 
pirical hypothesis. In our concluding chapters w’e will develop 
this possibility. Here we are concerned only to estimate and 
do justice to the important insight of logical positivism. This 
movement again makes clearly evident the a priori and formal 
element which abides in all theoretical knowledge, and indeed 
in all explicit description that makes use of language. Syntax, 
grammar, “the word” are always with us; and to use language 
is to affirm certain presuppositions of language, which impose 
themselves in this way upon all thought. 

So we are brought back after a full circle to the point where 
philosophy began in Greek antiquity. “In the beginning was 
the Logos” — there is no thought which is independent of logic. 
How shall we explain, what shall we deduce from this ubiquity 
of logical form.^. Shall we say that the dependence of thought 
upon logic is the Achilles’ heel of thought, because logic is 
merely verbal convention, just language, an arbitrary and sub- 
jective structure peculiar to man and human nature? This w^ay 
leads to skepticism. Or shall we say that nature itself finds voice 



POSITIVISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 523 

15. Planck, M., The Philosophy of Physics, trans. W. H. Johnston, 

New York, W. W. Norton and Company, Inc., 1936. 

16. Wittgenstein, L., Tractatus Logico-Philosophictis. New York, 

Harcourt, Brace and Company, 1922. 

17. Popper, K., The Logic of Discovery. Vienna, J. Springer, 1935. 

18. Carnap, R., The Unity of Science, trans. M. Black. London, 

George Routledge and Sons, 1934. 

19. Philosophy and Logical Syntax. London, George Rout- 

ledge and Sons, 1935. 

20. The Lo^cal Syntax of Language. New York, Harcourt, 

Brace and Company, 1937. 

21. Introduction to Semantics. Cambridge, Harvard Uni- 

versity Press, 1942. 

22. The Formalization of Logic. Cambridge, Harvard Uni- 

versity Press, 1943. 

23. Reichenbach, H., Experience and Prediction. Chicago, Univer- 

sity of Chicago Press, 1938. 

24. From Copernicus to Einstein. Boston, Longmans, Green 

and Company, 1942. 

2j. Elements of Symbolic Logic. New York, The Mac- 

millan Company, 1947. 

26. Morris, C. W., Loffcal Positivism, Pragniatisin, and Scientific 

Empiricism. Paris, Hermann and Company, 1937. 

27. Lewis, C. I., Mind and the World Order. New York, Charles 

Scribner’s Sons, 1929. 

28. Symbolic Loffc. New York, D. Applcton-Ccntury 

Company, Inc., 1933. 

29. Lewis, G. N., The Anatomy of Science. New Haven, Yale 

University Press, 1926. 

30. Frank, P., Between Physics and Philosophy. Cambridge, Har- 

vard University Press, 1941. 



THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THIS HISTORY 525 

in two of its aspects. We could not ay that every scientist 
has been a political liberal, nor that every political advance has 
consciously premised itself upon science. But on the whole, 
scientific and political progress have supported and stimulated 
each other. Together they have defined and propagated the 
sanity which is liberalism in thought and conduct. 

It is still convenient to divide the evolution of western 
civilization into three epochs, ancient, medieval, and modem. 
In some respects, the modem period does return to the intel- 
lectual ideals of antiquity. It again pursues a theoretical science, 
and establishes a constitutional form of government. But mod- 
em civilization is more different from antiquity than like it. 
Antiquity was rationalistic in its science and conservative in its 
politics. Modem society is empiricai in its science and progres- 
sive in its moral and political practice. Modem thought has 
recovered and absorbed ancient thought, but has subjected it 
to relentless criticism. This radical difference between modem 
and ancient society has its cause and explanation in the medieval 
centuries. 

When we say that the science of antiquity was rationalistic, 
we mean that science was then conceived to possess a core of 
absolute axioms, which supposedly were known to the reason 
independently of experience. This core of axioms was science 
net. Science gross contained in addition the many applicadons 
of this rational trath to particular fact. The human reason pro- 
vided science, the animal senses provided the material which 
was to be scientifically understood. And when we say that 
modem science is empirical, we mean that science is now con- 
ceived to consist of all of the generalizations which may be 
garnered from sensed fact. These generalizations may be 
woven together into organized theories; but the theories remain 
summaries of experienced fact, they are not regarded as rational 
and absolute traths. Whereas Greek science made rationally 
intuited principles the test of truth, modem science makes 
observed fact the test of trath. In this respect, the modem intel- 



THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THIS HISTORY 527 

they had deposed their kmgs and made the law their governor, 
with themselves the executors of the law. They were aware 
that their political liberty distinguished them from the “bar- 
barian” peoples about them, who still submitted to the personal 
despotism the Greeks have taught us to call “t3rraxmy.” Yet 
these tyrannies finally destroyed Greek freedom; and it is 
significant that the downfall of Greek liberty was due not to 
military defeat, but to certain internal weaknesses in Greek 
society. The Greeks could defeat imperial Persia; and th^ 
would have similarly repelled every invader, if they had not 
been destroyed from within by disunity and internecine strife. 
What defeated them was their failure to make their free 
and constitutional government the agency of political pr<^- 
ress. 

The rise and expansion of imperial Persia was not merely a 
military threat to the Greek cities. It was also a moral threat. 
There were those within the Greek cities who spontaneously 
prostrated themselves before that imperial might, and counseled 
their fellow citizens not to attempt resistance, but to appease 
and ally themselves with the irresistible invader. It required a 
loyalty religious in its intensity and almost fanatical in its 
courage to defy that advancing Persian tide. So the Greek 
leaders called upon their peoples for a religious fjuth in their 
institutions; and to establish or confirm them in their faith, the 
Greek statesman became a thinker, a scientist and •ohnosorher. 
He taught the Greeks that in defending their 
governments they only did what true religion required of them. 
The whole cosmos, he argued, is a constitution^ polity, ruled 
by a divine and universal law. In all of its motions, the cosmos 
manifests this eternal and immutable law. And to establish this 
religious truth, the Greek thinker created a natural science 
moving from observable fact to a theoretical knowledge of 
that cosmic structure which, he said, is natural and divine law'. 
The Logos, he taught, is the true God. The civic constitution 
is the Logos in its human context, and loyalty to constitutional 



THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THIS HIST<»Y 529 

always A successful faction imposes its will 

upon society, and claims for its legislative acts a moral or re- 
ligious sanctity which does not invest them, its actual authority 
being just sheer power. Law, they concluded, is only conven- 
tion, a usage or irr.pcsirior. without real authority. Justice is, 
the rule of the stronger; and the stronger may be the unscrupu- 
lous but skilful tyrant, the self-willed but able oligarchy, or 
the majority, individually w'eak but strong in their number. 
And the sophist was perhaps more willing than his opponent 
to put his thesis to the test of observable fact. Look at nature, 
he said, and you will see everywhere the rule of the stronger, 
the survival of the fittest, and the extermination of the weak. 
Nature is war, society is war, peace is a truce or a temporary 
balance of powers. There is no moral foundation for govern- 
ment because there is no moral law in nature — ^unless we give 
the name of moral law to this natural propriety by which the 
strong compels the weak. But in truth, according to the sophist, 
nature knows no law. Science has no authority. Only power 
has authority. 

The Greek thinker, struggling to meet and defeat this 
sophistry, never perceived its full strength. Failing to distin- 
guish the half-truth which lends it plausibility, he failed to 
detect clearly its error. The half-truth in sophistry, Greek or 
modem, is its recognition that poioer lies in individual things — 
and ultimately only there. The sophistic error *was to deduce 
from this correct premise the mistaken conclusion that the 
power of the individual precludes moral law and civic justice. 
The Greek thinker, in Im effort to combat the sophistic error, 
threw out both the error and the truth. Convinced of the 
cogency of his science, he now examined that science more 
intently, to discover wherein lay its generative insight. What he 
discovered was the theoretical form of science, which gives to 
science its unity, its stability, and whatever else distinguishes 
it from casual opinion. The error of the sophist, Parmenides 
decided, is that he ousts his senses. He sees individual things. 



the significance of this history 


531 

their near-emptiiiess they depict the concrete substance of 
truth. 

Plato made a valiant attempt to correct this Parmenidean 
metaphysics by compromising with the sophistic irrationalism. 
With Parmenides he agreed that the reason apprehends the 
eternal One; but naturd science, he said, arises when this ra- 
tional intuition is applied to the changing and particularized 
world of thmgs. Science is thus the rediscovery of eternal and 
universal form in the sensed particular changes of nature. This 
theory of knowledge, Plato sometimes implied, requires a 
dualisdc view of nature, which is properly conceived as being 
compounded of two sorts of being. One is the immutable 
Form, which Plato called “Being”; the other is motion itself, 
called by Plato “nonbemg.” In this Platonic dualism, the senses 
are allowed to provide the material of existent fact, in which 
the Being apprehended by reason is variously, inccanpletcly, 
and transiendy manifested. So sensory knowledge and em- 
pirical science are not sheer illusion, but a confused and imr 
perfect version of radonal knowledge. 

Plato seemed to have saved the Greek faith in the “intellect,” 
i.e. in theoredcal reason. He turned back the dde of overt 
skepdcism, which did not rally again for two thousand years. 
Because this Greek metaphysics also defined eternal Being as 
divine and Good, it saved ^ the profounder Greek faith in 
the idendty of intellectual and moral truth. The' reason, intuit- 
ing the Being which is the origin of all intelligible structure 
in the world, discovers those true forms which are the proper 
destinies or ends of natural motions. Everything seeks to mani- 
fest its true form; and since these forms are all redprocally ad- 
justed, as aspects of the one Being, this effort of things to 
realize their forms sustains the vast and eternal economy of 
nature. 

But if Greek metaphysics saved the letter of intellectual and 
moral faith, it did not save natural science, which is the full 
confession of this faith. It allowed the senses to illustrate the 



the significance of this history 


553 

pessimian investing pagan civilization, which evinced itself 
in a nostalgia for the remote and golden past, iinaily possessed 
itself of the Greek spirit in this otherworldly, transcendental 
Platonism. The later Greeks, in particular the Stoics, no longer 
distinguished ideal justice from universal cosmic law; and this 
had the advantage of detaching the concept of justice from 
the city-state, to make it the concept of a universal moral law, 
antecedent to all government and independent of it. But the 
“blessed city of God” of the Stoics, although it contained all 
who acknowledged its moral government, was still an invisable 
realm, not to be sought in political actualities. Greek meta- 
physics was the consolation of a defeated and conquered peo- 
ple, who magnified their dream of a justice they could no longer 
hope to possess. 

This consolatory metaphysical dream became philosophy, 
became even “science,” and remained this for two millennia. 
No wonder that under later antiquity a rebellion moved against 
the Greek formalism that had become so unrealistic. Chrikiaa- 
ity made this rebellion vocal and effective, when it turned 
from theoretical to religious symbolism, in order to announce 
its optimistic gospel of salvation come to earth. 

Greek metaphysics seemed to weather this storm of religious 
revolution. It emerged again in Christian theology and in a 
scholastic philosophy auxiliary to theology. Early Christianity 
had looked beyond the law to prophetic revelation, beyond the 
state to the congregation united by caritas or love, and beyond 
cosmic structure to the creative power which fashioned struc- 
ture even in creating matter. But Greek legalism restored itself 
in a feudal eccleSiasticism, Greek formali^ restored itself in 
a Platonic theology. Finally, however, in the Reformation and 
its consequences, the Christian revolution against pagan thought 
was consummated, to produce the science, the political theory 
and practice, and the emancipated society of the modem world. 

There was really but one reform, one rebirth, one revolt; 
ushering in this modem world. It was the revolt which trans- 



537 


the SiranFICANCE OF THIS HISTORY 

ever? “Natural rights” means underived and absolute powers. 
The concept of natural law may conceivably be derived from 
the concept of indiiddual rights— whether it can be so derived 
is a question. But neither the concept of natural rights, nor the 
actuality of natural rights, is derivable from the concept of 
natural law. What our fathers meant, when they used the 
familiar verbiage of natural law to establish natural rights, was 
that the existence of individual rights is an absolute and non- 
debatable axiom. The individual is de£ned as the possessor of 
inalienable rights. 

We are now beginning to see how the problem facing 
modem society must be stated. We must ask; How does one 
establish this principle of individual natural rights? The 
foimders of modem government believed the principle to be 
a rational intuition, self-evident and infallible. They placed it 
beyond debate, exactly as we place beyond debate Ae truth 
that one and one are two. Yet we see that it cannot literally be 
placed beyond dispute. It is even now disputed; and there seems 
to be some evidence, provided by a scientific and empirical 
study of social process, against its trath. Can this evidence be 
outweighed? Or, even better, can it be anal5rzed, and discov- 
ered not to disprove, but to confirm more surely than ever, 
the principle of individual rights upon which modem justice 
has established itself? 

It can be analyzed and shown to confirm the democratic 
principle. But to do this, we must undertake an analyas which 
goes deeper than what is ordinarily called scientific analysis. 
We must undertake philosophical analysis that probes to a truth 
which is implicidy obeyed and applied by all science, and 
which is indeed generative of science. We have to penetrate 
to philosophical truth. Our motive in seeking this truth is 
political — ^we wish to assure ourselves of the righteousness of 
democratic government. But we find that pliilosophical truth 
also conditions our faith in science. Democratic theory or prac- 
tice, we find, is not subject to criticism upon any ground of 



the significance of this history 


539 

fact to submit to the necessities of logic, such submisaon bdiw 
the necessary and sufficient condition of the theoretical formu- 
lation of fact in science. But hoio, on the showing of Hume 
that we find no necessity in nature, do we justify Ms seenmg 
asswnption that nature is subject to logical necessity? Is not 
this predication to nature of logical conformity just a con- 
venient fiction? What evidence is there that nature is somehow 
inherendy logical? How do we harmonize this rational de- 
mand, that particular fact shall always conform to some theory, 
with our empirical insistence that particular fact may be any- 
thing we observe it to be? 

Modem civilization seems to stand rooted in paradojc. The 
individual, we say, is soverei^; yet he is, of course, bound by 
a constitution which prescribes and limits the exercise of his 
sovereignty. Particular fact, we say, is the source and miifrio n 
of true theory, even as the individual is the source and the 
criterion of just law; yet particular fact may not transgress the 
requirements of logic, nor reject the conditions of its theoret- 
ical comprehension by the scientist. The constimtion still Hmitv 
individual freedom, logic still limits hypothesis and faa. We 
live in self-contradiction, holding the individual to be at once 
free yet bound, holding particular fact to be and not to be the 
sole criterion of truth. 

Might we not say that this self-contradiction has worked 
well, and justified itself in practice? Has not the democratic 
constitution supported a century and a half of liberal and 
progressive legislation? Has not the logical constimtion of 
science permitted the fullest accommodation of theoretical 
hypothesis to particular and observed occurrence? Why 
worry? Why not accept, as a mystery which somehow sup- 
ports all that is intelligible and good, this self-contradiction at 
the root of science and society? 

Because this paradox which has underlain modem theory 
and practice is today the source of intellectual, moral and 
political confusion, to a degree that threatens civilization itself. 



the significance of this history 


54 * 

tore. Our best reason is our most comprehensive summary of 
particular facts. 

There is no doubt of the truth of Hume’s contention, and no 
defense against his critical polemic. Yet if his truth were the 
whole truth, there would be possible no distinction between 
human science and animal cognition. The higher animalg whose 
sensory faculties most resemble our own should also be phya- 
cists and chemists, and speculate concerning canine or oAer 
freedom. What Hume neglected was the agency in science of 
language, with all that language implies. He overlooked the 
cognitive interest, and did not appreciate the logical instru- 
mentalities which this interest has generated. 

So Kant attempted to correct Hume’s error without sacrifice 
of Hume’s truth. Science, he said, is the effort of the cognitive 
will to unify experience. It brings to this task the agencies 
which are reason. These are internal to mmd; and we may take 
note of them in the explicit and necessary axioms, e.g. those of 
mathematics, which are basic to all description. Science is com- 
pounded on the one hand of contingent and particular fact, but 
on the other hand of the rational forms which bring this mate- 
rial into theoretical system. But on what evidence do we 
believe that this imposition of mental forms produces a sdenoe 
truly descriptive of external reality? There is no evidence, Kant 
concluded. We cannot suppose that science describes reality as 
it is in itself. The world described by science is a phenomenal 
world; it is appearance, not reality. The true or noumenal 
reality is known to us only in moral judgment. This is imme^ 
diate, final, and absolute; but it grasps only the particular situa- 
tion regulated by the moral act, Kant did justice to the rational 
element in science, but only at the sacrifice of our faith in the 
power of science to describe reality. 

There followed the metaphysicians, who made Elands failure 
to establish scientific truth their excuse for a return to dog- 
matism. Hume and Kant have shown, they argued, that em- 
pirical science reaches only phenomenal knowledge, which is 



the significance of this history 

truth or to attempt justice, we must be able to say what “truth” 
and “justice” mean. And to define these terms in such a way as 
to leave truth and justice accessible to man is to say something 
absolute and incontrovertible about this world, in which truth 
is sought and justice aspired to. What is this aWute or philo- 
sophical truth which makes reasonable the pursuits of 
knowledge and justice? 

We are now ready to undertake successful assault upcm this 
problem, which has hitherto defeated philosophical inquiry. Its 
solution, we have learned, requires us to establish the identity 
of the empirical and logical criteria of truth, the false distinc- 
tion of which has hitherto prevented the reconciliation of 
rationalism, emphasizing the logical criterion, with empiricism, 
emphasizing the criterion of fact. Science requires hypotheas 
to be at once logically self-consistent and conastent with 
observed particular fact. We need to know that these two 
demands can both be fulfilled in a single hypothesis, and that 
the satisfaction of one demand does not preclude that of the 
other. What we shall show is that there are not two demands. 
There is in truth only one requirement, which is at once 
rational and empirical. Logic, we shall show, only implements 
the empirical requirement that hypothesis shall conform to dl 
observed fact. It is the word “all” that generates logic— logic 
secures impartiality and comprehensiveness of hypotheas. TTie 
logical requirement is the demand that the empirical require- 
ment be fully satisfied, and not satisfied only in part. The solu- 
tion is as simple as that. This is the conjunction of reason and 
sense, fulfilling the moral requirement of justice or impartiality. 

So we shall bring to an end the ancient controversy between 
rationalism and empiricism, and establish at last the truthful- 
ness of science and the power of the human intellect to reach a 
realistic knowledge. The controversy was not fruitless, because 
it was the necessary preparation for this reconciliation. The 
reconciliation demonstrates the simple but solemn truth, stated 
long ago by Socrates — ^that intelligence and righteousness are 



27 THE ESTABLISHMENT 

OF PHILOSOPHICAL TRUTH 


T 

XN THIS CHAPTER WE BRING THE DEVELOPMENT OT 

philosophy to a successful issue by resolving die 
problem which has defeated past thought* ^ence requires 
hypothesis to conform to fact, yet seems also to insist that fact 
shall conform to logical necesaty. Democratic govennacat 
affirms the sovereignty of the individual, yet seems also to 
require that the individual submit to law. Why should par^ 
ticular fact defer to the requirements of logic? How should a 
sovereign individual submit to law? 

There can, we intimated, be only one resolution of this 
problem. The two requirements, apparently contradictoty, 
must resolve into one and the same requirement. This has 
usually been perceived, and the philosopher has attempted to 
show either that the logical and legal requirement includes 
the other (rationalism) or that the logical and legal require^ 
ment is not valid (empiricism). But this contempt of one oc 
the other requirement led only to mterminable cootrwecsy 
between opposed schools of thought* 

In modem times the problem has been beclouded by a mis* 
conception common to both schools. Because it was clear that 

545 



the establishment of philosophical troth 547 

have inquired into its philosophical implicarions. The inertia of 
past intellectual habit makes such inquiry difficult, even for 
those whose labors initiate the new conception- Usually a 
generation has to pass, and another generation grow to matu- 
rity in the new way of thinking, before the full implication 
of a revolutionary hypothesis is seen. 

The revolution we refer to is popularly associated with the 
ncme. of Einstein, and properly so, although many others have 
participated in it. We may define it as a departure from cer- 
tain of the principles of the “clasacal” science of Newton- It 
might be called the inauguration of romantic science, usar^ 
the word “romantic” somewhat in its literary or aesthetic 
sense. 

We are not concerned here, fortunately, with the whole 
current and consequence of this revolution in phyacal sdenoe. 
Our concern is limited to one point, namely the imffficatian of 
the new science for our conception of the relation between 
mathematical theory and the science of phyacal nature. The 
effect of the Emsteinian hypothesis is to prov^ a new and 
liberating insight into the relation of physicd sdence to mathe- 
matical theory. Since the time of Parmemdes, U. the fifth 
century b.c., it had been assumed that ph^cal hypothec m^ 
defer to mathematical theory. The axioms of 
were held to be absolute self-evident truths vouched for by the 
reason itself. We must agree that these axioms seei^ self- 
evident; and prior to Einstem there had fa^ estaWuiwd no 
instance railing into question their exact applicability to natiOT. 
Plato, it is true, aUowed that nature, because of its mate^ 
element, might fall short of exact confonnity to maihemati^ 
necessity; but Descartes and the modems were more strirt, 
and required the exact conformity of observable fact m ma^ 
matical principles. It is this uncompromismg i%or of modem 
science that has led to the correction of its an<^ error. 

Until our own century, then, mathemaoesd ration^ 
seemed invulnerable. Mathematical axioms seemed rational and 



THE ESTABLISHMENT OF PHILOSOPHICAL 'raUTH 


549 


they were strange difEcuk to handle, the minute meas- 
urements testing their approximation to fact were not at that 
time practicable, and Euclidean geometry satisfied every scien- 
tific need; therefore they were placed on the shelf of mathemat- 
ical curiosities. However, even the construction of these new 
geometries was disproof of Kant’s contention that Euclidean 
geometry rests on a priori synthetic principles; for the new 
geometries rest equally upon “self-evident principles,” identical 
with those of the old geometry; and the several geometries, 
new and old, cannot all be true. 

This conclusion was empirically confirmed early in the 
century when Einstein and his successors revived the non- 
Euclidean geometries, using them as alternative and divergent 
hypotheses in the description of physical fact. It was found 
that Euclidean geometry sufficiently defines ph)^cal morion 
only in certain limited cases; and the physicist in hk most 
general hypotheses now creates his geometry to order, in the 
fight of empirical fact. Geometry, in short, is henceforth physir 
cd hypothesis, not rational intuition of self-evident tra^ 

This removed geometry from the domain of “rational 
science”; but arithmetic remained. It could still be argued that 
arithmetical principles constitute a domain of rationri knowl- 
edge, necessarily applicable to all parricular fact. If «>, arith- 
metic would still provide the needed evidence that there exists 
a faculty of rational intuition, independent of and superior 
to empirical hypothesis. 

That arithmetic does not comprise a science of this sort was 
shown by Russell and Whitehead, whose logical studies were 
contemporaneous with the developmmt of the physical theory 
of relativity which so transformed geometry. These two 
thinkers invalidated Kant’s contention that arithmetical prop- 
ositions are at once a priori and synthetic, which would 
mean that they are self-evident or necessary truths descriptive 
of universal nature. The Principin M/ttbetustics ^owed that 
number-theory can be reduced to, or r^laced by, a ^istem of 



the establishment of philosophical truth 


55 * 

such a symbolic system, and develop geometrical symbolism 
purely as logicians and without thought of the descriptive truth 
or falsity of the system; and such study is “pure geometry” 
or “mathematics.” But we may also consider geometry as 
descriptive hypothesis, and study its conformity to physical 
or astrophysical fact; and when we do this, we are empirical 
scientists. This profitable division of labor into analjrtical and 
experimental studies should be exercised in every theoretical 
science, the lopcian developing symbolic systems, and the 
empirical scientist applying and testing these systems in field 
and laboratory. 

But we are not so much concerned with the new scientific 
developments opened up by this recent intellectual revolution, 
important though these are, as with its implication for philo- 
sophical truth. Its immediate philosophical coiise<][nence is its 
decisive verdict against rationalistic philosophy in favor of 
empirical philosophy. 

There is, it makes clear, no self-evident rational knowl«%e, 
at least of the sort pretended. Our only knowledge of nature 
is empirical knowledge, comprised of hypotheses of high 
probability. Logic and mathematics are not natural knowled^ 
but constitute an art of symbolic construction or notation; and 
any descriptive character they may possess derives from the 
empirical material from which then: logical elements were 
originally abstracted. It will be some time, perhaps, before this 
implication is widely perceived and becomes a cmnmoiiplace 
of thought. Old errors live on, and rationalistic metaphyacians 
will still advance a “concrete logic.” But there can be little 
doubt of the issue. The newly enfranchised' sdence and the 
expanded “mathematical logic” are here to stay; and their 
implications will steadily become evident. 

But this is only half the story. Admitting that neirfjer logic 
nor mathematics nor any other “rational sdence” msy confirm 
scientific hypothesis or prescribe to empirical science; admit- 
ring that language, with the Itgic which is the syntax of laa-r 



the establishment of philosophical truth 


553 

and replaced hy a new theoretical hypothesis conastem with 
the recalcitrant fact. 

Thus the effect of logic, stated in its simplest terms, is to 
ensure that aU observed fact shall have its due place in the 
symbolic construction which is scientific theory, and that no 
particular fact shall be disfranchised. The symbolic construc- 
tion which is the logic of a science does not express a concern 
for logic and symbolization as such. These are only mpanc to 
scientific impartiality toward fact. 

Logic implements empirical impartiality toward observed 
particular fact. This is its sole scientific function, as is demon- 
strated in two ways. First, the scientist holds no brief for any 
specific hypothesis as such, but he is always willing, just insofar 
as he is an authentic scientist, to relinquish a theory which fails 
to meet all of the evidence. He is not interested in theory as 
such, he is interested in theory only as a device enabling - the 
impartial accommodation of fact. Secondly, the scientist does 
not insist upon, and no longer expects to find, a shigie theory 
covering all fact. Modem theoretical science is incorrigibly 
pluralistic, advancing physical theory, bioli^cal dieory, social 
and psychological theory simultaneously and in independence 
of one another. This relinquishment of the old rationalisac 
goal of a single universal theory implicitly affirms the aoxiiiaiy 
character of theoretical form and the instrumental character 
of logic. If logical unity were an end or objective in itself, the 
plurality of theories would be an indictment convicting science 
of error — ^which is just what the rationalist frequently con- 
siders it. But modem science, subservient only to evidence, has 
substantially established the truth that natural processes present 
diverse sfractures requiring for their description many theories, 
not only one. There is, science increasingly assures ns, no sing^ 
theory of nature. 

We reach here the momentous fact that is the solution of our 
problem. The two criteria of truth, logic and particular fact, 
are really one and the same criterion. Trae rationalism is em- 



THE ESTABLISHJVIENT OF PHILOSOPHICAL TRUTH 

555 

value, we know, are characters of real being, and real beiiw is 
individud being. It follows that real value is by definition 
diflferentiated. Value is difference, not sameness; nonconform- 
ity, not orthodo^. Individuality alone has value. The ration- 
alistic identification of value with likeness or structural unity, 
which in modem times has generated the absolute and totali- 
tarian state, is finally a blasphemy against justice, truth, and 
God. Justice looks beyond sameness in order to appredatse indi- 
vidual character, truth looks beyond identity in order to per- 
ceive particular difference, God knows each creature in its 
individual uniqueness. Yet the blasphemy was well meant; and 
it was correct enough in its assumption that logic somehow indi- 
cates the moral nature of nature, and unplements our apprehen- 
sion of the morality of nature. The rationalistic error was to 
mistake the nature and function of logic. It is n«: logic, we 
saw, which requires the comprehension of nature nndf-r a single 
theoretical hypothesis. Neither logic nor the logician requites 
nature to be imified, homogeneous, same. Logic demands noth- 
ing in the way of description or definition of nature; it ensnres 
only that our statement of fact, whatever it be, shall neglect no 
fact. Or rather, it ensures this impartial comprehenaveness 
fact if we will first, prior to all analysis, set ourselves to do just- 
ice to all fact. If we will be just and empirical, logic will imple- 
ment our wiU; but if we want to be dogmatic and unjust, logic 
will no less subserve the elaboration of rationalistic tystems, 
which may be imposed upon facts and upcm men as sanctified 
truth. Logic is indifferently the tool of truth and of error. But 
we would be unjust to logic if we emphasized its susceptibility 
to abuse at the expense of our appreciation of its great service. 
Given the will to truth, logic implements that wilL Thtis 
is justified Augustine, who established a new civilization upon 
the primacy of the will. 

What is the will to truth? It is the will to do justice to 
each and every particular fact. What is particular fact? It is our 
apprehension of individual being at some time and place. All 



557 


THE ESTABLISHMENT OF PHILOSOPHICAL TRUTH 

is effectiveness, power. The force and quality of every par- 
ticular action determine those of the particular reaction.^c£nj- 
mon sense and justice equally require a respect for particular 
fact and individual being. Prudence and kindness are ultimately 
one. Every injustice done to individual being of necessity 
recoils upon the doer; and every mercy blesses him that gives 
no less than him who takes. 

This is the moral law of nature, as it is that of society. It is 
the meaning of the metaphysical truth which affirms the reality 
of individual being, and in consequence denies the reality of 
“universal being.” These last two words are meaningless, un- 
thinkable; they comprise a self-contradiction. There is no um- 
versal being, there are only individual beings which in some 
respects, but in no case in all reqiects, may be similar. The 
rejects in which things are similar or disamilar must be deter- 
mined by observation and eiqjeriment;’ and that is why em- 
pirical science must be the rule of life, of sodety, and of God. 

After six centuries, we have justified the doctrme of the 
medieval nominalists whose real work, we remember, was the 
establishment of empirical science. The nominalist denied the 
reality of universal being in the interests of individual bemg^ 
but he was unable to do justice to the power of theoretical 
knowledge. General ideas, he averred, exist only in the mind; 
and this was to leave sdence without claim to objective truth. 
We correct this error when we acknowledge the existence of 
real similarities among individual things. If simiiarit^ are not 
real, how should specific and individual differences be real? 

We discover herein the integrity of modem thought Skice 
Roscellinus, Grosseteste, Roger Bacon, Duns Scotus, and their 
successors initiated modem thought, there has moved forward 
this single faith in the absoluteness and primaiy of individual 
being. Out of it has been built an empirical science and an 
industrial economy. Out of it has been generated a democratic 
society, pledged to equalitarian justice among men. These two 
developments are truly one. A sodety whhh industrializes 



the establishment of philosophical truth 


559 

planation of specific similarities. There arises the quesdon, stili 
empirical but philosophical in its breadth, why there should be 
similarity at aU, of any sort. The Greek philosophers asked this 
question, but would not wait for an answer. They replied at 
once: It is of the essence of nature to present sinularities; for 
nature is truly one, and its identity appears, compounded with 
difference, in similarities. 

But this is false. The true essence of nature is individuality 
or difference of character. Similarity is overlaid. That tl« 
inquiry into the causes of similarity is a sigiuficant, possible, 
and profitable inquiry is demonstrated by every causal hypoth- 
esis; but it was given a new and strilmg significance when 
Darvrin showed that every organic siniilarity is the coa- 
sequence of the mode of reproduction of living organisins, as 
these are influenced by their environment. By a.«Jnrtg this 
philosophical question about similarity in one spedai field, 
Darwin revolutionized biology. But the question must be car- 
ried into every field, and be asked finally of nature at large, 
until we learn at last something of the creative power that has 
moved in all things to fabricate this world. For we are inteiufed 
to know even as God knows, in naked truth, and not “sec 
through a glass, darkly.” 



SCIENCE AND GOVEBUSTMENT 


S6i 

respect both to its intensity and to its objective, from their 
free religion, which imposed upon the individual a religious 
and moral responsibility not to be delegated to Ving or gover- 
nor. Accordingly, the revolutionary founders of the first 
modem republic, the short-lived Commonwealth, stated their 
political faith in religious terms. Such statement would still be 
fitting. We still hold liberty of conscience and thought to be 
the primary freedoms, generating all others; but the religions 
terminology would be invidious and misleading today, espe- 
cially among peoples still intellectually dominated by audior- 
itarian religion. 

It is this selfsame religious faith, however, vidiich finds its 
authentic statement in philosophical truth. There is but one 
Truth, capable of infinite variety in its formulation. Religious 
mysticism, which is what most modems mean by religion, is 
the illuminated perception of the holiness which everywhere 
invests individual being, i.e. reality. Philosophy corrects ration- 
alistic theology when it translates this ineffable mystical experi- 
ence into the sober statement, “Reality is individt^ being," and 
proceeds to enlarge this simple trath into a descr^tivc science. 
We still expound in this science the faith of those who maugu- 
rated modem government; but the word “faith” now loMS its 
equivocal meaning. It no longer means a belief transcen^ng 
reason, knowledge, science. It means the truth which generates 
reason, Icnowledge, and science. 

It scarcely need be elaborated further that philosophical 
trath, so far from being something that eludes demotetration, 
is implicitly demonstrated in every demonstration of fact 
whatsoever. Every scientific hypothesis applies ths truth, and 
in its confirmation confirms it; nor does any descripuon of 
fact have meaning or truth except in virtue of that one truth. 
Every practical program has moral claim and final e&czcy m 
the degree to wluch it is an acknowledgment of all of the indi- 
viduals affected by it. Every work of art owes its beauty and 
significance to the artist’s perception and successful com- 



SCIENCE AND GOVERNMENT 


563 

political achievement. The great universe itself, diey asscrteil, 
is a political community ruled by natural law. Significant, 
surely, is the parallel between the political decline of Greece 
and the transformation of this Greek science into an unreal- 
istic metaphysics. It is because Parmenides suspected, and 
Plato saw, the failure of Greek government that diese men 
looked beyond an empirical science descriptive of actually to 
a transcendent science descriptive of a Being which “fe” yet 
does not exist. Because they wimessed political they 

renounced that faith in actual justice which had inspired the 
earlier scientists. They could not or would not see that the 
cause of Greek distress was the smallness of their sovereign 
city-states, and the confined and obstructed justice which this 
entailed. They could not agree, accordingly, that the doom of 
their cities, admittedly inevitable, was alM just. And with tiuB 
failure of moral reali^ went a failure of cognifive or sdeo- 
rific realism, a hardening of empirical inquiry into an ntpres- 
sive but sterile metaphy^cs. 

The parallel is seldom quite so clear in later timwi, chiefly 
because the intellectual habits of the Greeks (Or shouy we 
say their vocabulary?) were retained by peoples pf^ltxsdl^ 
undeveloped. We should see that Greek morality, as thk 
appeared in their political institutions, was as astonishii^fy' 
beyond that of other peoples as was their science. Yet there is 
observable a loose but discernible connection between the 
feudal and ecclesiastical hierarchy of the Middle Ages and the 
medieval predilecdon for Neoplatonic and Aristotelian hier- 
archies of forms. Again apparent and striking, however, is the 
historical connection in the modem period between the devel- 
opments of empirical science and democratic govenunenn Oar 
purpose here is not to review this historical paraHel, hot to 
diagnose and understand it as it works today. 

Modern democracy differs from Greek democracy in liat 
it places the individual above the law as the maker of law, 
whereas liberty meant to the Greeks a ctanmon and equdi srf>- 



SCIENCE AND GOVERNMENT 


565 

We have seen how the past confusion of logic with empirical 
hypothesis has limited and confined science. So long as 
geometry was conceived to be “pure mathematics,” i.e. a study 
resting on absolute and self-evident axioms, its postulates were 
incumbent upon the scientist, and hypotfiesis had to r emain 
within its framework. No hypothesis might be advanced, none 
was conceivable, which violated those principles. When scien- 
tists broke through this confinement by their acceptance of 
non-Euclidean geometries, they demonstrated that geometry is 
not pure but applied mathematics, le. empirical hypothesis; and 
this ended at least the old confurion of the logical or theoretical 
form of geometry with the descriptive material so informed. 
“Pure mathematics” we now see to be a synonym for “logic^” 
a study of symbolic systems viewed in their formal clarity and 
in abstraction from any consideration of these systems in their 
descriptive use. To distinguish in a scientific theory the logical 
or formal element from the descriptive, empirical, or material 
element is to liberate hypothesis; because one and the same 
logic can now be compoimded with an indefinite numbtf of 
descriptive elements, to produce a variety of self-consistent 
descriptive theories. These theories are thmi alternative hypoth- 
eses, susceptible to confirmation or disproof in the %ht of 
observable fact. 

The confusion of logic with descriptive theory limits hy- 
pothesis to an “orthodox” field of speculation; but what are the 
positive effects of this confinement, and what suggests or 
motivates the confusion? Generally, it is just the result of intel- 
lectual inertia, and has no positive motive. It is difScnlt, even or 
especially for the scientist, to change those broadest descriptive 
principles which have directed all past analysis. To change 
these requires him to create new intellectual habits. Yet, be- 
cause science is finally motivated by love of truth, it is chiefly 
scientists who have escaped from dogma and initiated new 
ways of thought. It is usually others than scientists who have 
sought to confine empirical hypotheris and intellectnal progress 



SCIENCE AND GOVERNMENT 


567 

There the confusion of logic with descriptive hypothesis is 
seen to involve the neglect of some body of particular fact, in 
the interests of some favored body of fact. In practical matters, 
judgment is seldom so easy; but the dogmatist usually betrays 
his prejudice by admitting that his dogma involves injustice to 
some individuds, and arguing that this is excused by some 
larger good consequent upon it. But justice, which is philo- 
sophical truth, forbids such casuistry. It requires the iitll 
acknowledgment of every individual claim, not imly of 
or of most. It requires acknowledgment of individuak past and 
gone, of individuals now living, of individuals yet to be. The 
principle acknowledges no limitation of time and space. The 
only limit is the actual one, our relative ignorance of individual 
being. But this confession of ignorance excuses no dismissal of 
known fact. Moral responsibility is absolute and uncoinprcHai^ 
ing. 

To defeat dogma and enthrone justice, modem sodety 
created the democratic constitution. As the intention and effect 
of logic is to secure living contact between hypothesis and 
particular occurrence, so the intention and effect of this con- 
stimtion is to secure the living repercussion upon government 
and legislation of the individuals governed. To understand its 
efficacy, compare the democratic constitution with nondemo- 
cratic constitutions. Every people has its political constitution, 
written or unwritten, because “constitution” means the haffit- 
ual procedure dete rmining the appointment of govOTiment, the 
sources and limits of legislation, etc. The constitution of a non- 
democratic society is quite simply one which intnets the 
responsibilities and powers of government to some group fewer 
in number than the whole people. It is perhaps irrdevant to 
justice whether this group rules wisely or foolishly, beiev- 
olently or malevolently, in order to presave hereditary 
privilege or in order to inaugurate utopia. Such govemnient is 
unjust, however “good” or “bad” it be, because it violates tiie 
first requirement of justice, which is ttot every human beti^ 



SaENCE AND GOVERNMENT 


5^9 

would injure or destroy it. Our first objective in govemmeat 
should be minimum govenunent, leaving a mayinniTn sphere to 
freedom, persuasion, and education. However, there can be set 
no formal limits to government. The intention of the constitu- 
tion should be to secure to every individual his participation in 
government and his voice in legislation. The conditions secur- 
ing this franchise will vary with social progress. What provides 
these conditions belongs in the constitution; what does not has 
no place in the constitution. Constitutional law is not in its 
formal prescription eternal law. What is eternal in it is its 
purpose, which is to secure the conditions of self-government. 
If it should be found, for example, that an extreme maldistribu- 
tion of wealth defeats the intention of the constitution, then 
the legal correctives of that evil should appear as constitutional 
amendments. It is not debatable, however, that government 
should be limited in its every dealing by “due process of law," 
because whatever violates that edict is done arbitrarily and 
illegally. Just government is necessarily constimtional govern- 
ment, or government by law; for there exists no device other 
than legislation which allows a plurality of individuals to estab- 
lish and enforce a cooperative decision. It follows, finally, that 
the final arbitrament must be that of the court of law, be- 
cause it is there, and only there, that the law of the land, includ- 
ing its constitutional law, is called into effective operation. The 
division of government into three branches is not a device to 
limit government by reciprocal checlcs and controls; it b the 
necessary mechanism by which a people makes, implements, 
and applies its law. 

Democratic government is today the chief means by which 
the individual exercises his moral responsibility. TTus regtonti- 
bility is not limited by national boundaries, it is to and for all 
men everywhere. It is evident that our political acts ^ect the 
lives of individuals in other nations. In a democratic world, 
national polities would be jurisdictional districts a^ not 
sovereign states. There is truly no soverogn state, there is truly 



SCIENCE AND GOVERNMENT 


57t 

movement which in Britain and America proceeded to poKtical 
revolution, it may be argued, had its wide origins in the popular 
spread of the Franciscan brotherhood in the thirteenth century. 
However this may be, there is no question of the fact that the 
establishment of democratic liberty by means of a written con- 
stitution preceded by more than a century the complete en- 
franchisement of science. This latter has occurred only in oar 
own time. It is only today, in virtue of the clear and explide 
distinction between formal logic and descriptive science, that 
empirical hypothesis is finally freed from the last dogmatic 
shackles which confined it. 

Now that science is finally freed from the sheath of dt^gma 
which had protected its immaturity, science may properly be 
the support of intelligent practice. Its first assignment is to 
illuminate our understanding of the relation of constituticmal 
to other law. If we lose faith in the democratic constitution, it 
will be because this constitution seems to require “interpreta- 
tion” dictated by what is vaguely referred to as “different 
social philosophies.” This is the vocabulary of intellectual and 
political skepticism; and there is no question that a succession 
of court majorities widely diverging in “social philosophy” and 
in their consequent legal decisions will weaken faith in demo- 
cratic justice. Yet what is the alternative? So long as our own 
G)nstitution is fixed, must it not by some expedient be made to 
fit the facts, i.e. conform to social actualities? Of course it must. 
Not to conform would be finally to become discredited as an 
agency of justice, and to be thrown off. Yet how can it be 
t^own off? A people ruled by law must abide by law. It must 
somewhere, either in a Supreme Court or in some lower court, 
accept the jurisdiction of law. To throw off the Constitution 
would be to live by no constitution, and no longer live by law; 
and this means, whatever one pleases to call it, a person^ <fic- 
tatorship by some permanent or transimt group usurping 
justice. 

Our error has been to think of the Constitution as fixed, and 



SaENCE AND GOVERNMENT 


S73 

confined within that one form or logic. It is free to cast new 
forms, even new logical forms. Let us establish this last free- 
dom! 

We said that geomeoy had disclosed itself to be empirical 
hypothesis, whereas arithmetic had disclosed itself to be a 
purely logical system or notation. This statement was rou^y 
correct, but not the whole truth. The several geometries 
in certain only of their generative postulates, other postulates 
remaining formally identical in all. These identical postulates, 
disclosed by formal analysis, comprise the “logic” of such 
geometry as we now have. This does not mean, however, that 
there is no other logic or notation useful in the description of 
physical nature. As a matter of fact, ph)rsical science makes 
very great use of norigeometrical logic, for example in quantum 
mechanics; and the next rather terrf)dng re^onsibility of the 
physical scientist, to which Einstein and others already devote 
themselves, is the creation of a single notational system or 
“logic” which will replace these two notations now in use. 

Similarly we should not suppose that arithmetic or number- 
theory, whatever its “purely logical” status, defines forever the 
largest outline of numerical form. Mathematicians such as those 
who develop the theory of groups already explore beyond 
these confines. There was a time when mathematical lo^c, or 
arithmetic, forbade the notion of fractions not to be ^resed 
as a ratio of two integers, forbade the notion of nothing, for- 
bade the notion of negative quantities, and forbade many an- 
other notion now familiar to the mathematical student. Arith- 
metical progress has been a continuous re-creation of notational 
logic — ^the only sort of logic we know. 

So it is with the democratic constitution. The modem ftffm 
is not that of the Greeks. The Constitution of the United States 
is not the original Constitution, which has been subjected 
to amendments each of which modifies the mcanmg of ^ the 
Constitution as a whole. What we need accordingly k a 
political science which will do for constitutional law what the 



IV THE FUTURE 



29 THE FUTURE OF SCIENCE 


philosophical truth is its enfranchisement of science* 
through the complete liberation of empirical hypothesis. Even 
the astounding scientific achievement of the last half century 
proceeded under a rationalistic handicap. This was the assump- 
tion that science is a superstructure built upon a fixed founda- 
tion of obligatory principles, or committed to a single definable 
“method.” Many books are published professing to present 
scientific method; but examination reve^ these to be only a 
confused conglomerate of logical formulas and current hy- 
potheses, cemented by vague discussions of probability, induc- 
tion, and verification. In truth, the only concHton impend upon 
scientific speculation is conformity to the two criteria of 
knowledge, logic and fact. Sufficient understanding of fonml 
logic may allow the scientist to estimate within his special 
field the powers and limitations of current scientific langnage, 
a perception which might enable him to ^tend the scoj^ of 
his hypothesis; but the scientist is seldom hindered by any inca- 
pacity of logical power. The physical scientist obttins in his 
mathematical training a competence in logic surpassing that of 
any save the most expert logicians; and every ^ appropriaaon 
of scientific theory involves large understanding of Ic^cal 

577 



the future of scienc:k 

ceptions blind us to individual quality, and thereby destroy 
society. 

What is the truth in this assertion? There is no truth in it. 
We have seen that the primary principle of science is its em- 
pirical regard for particular fact, and that this regard for par- 
ticular fact activates a moral reverence for individual being. 
If there is any way of thought which does not mechanke 
thought and which properly esteems individual character, that 
way of thought is thereby scientific. 

Why therefore docs the lie flourish, whence derives its 
plausibility? Its plausibility derives from a confusion of scien- 
tific thought with scientific formulas. Scientific theories are 
large and complex generalizations, defining certain widespread 
characters of natural processes. Necessarily, general theory 
abstracts in its statement from much particular difference. The 
moralist, who is no scientist busy with the creation and applica- 
tion of theoretical hypotheses, and whose knowledge of science 
is culled from hearsay or textbooks, may suppose science to 
present its theories as themselves a final description of namre; 
and if he does so, he may well conclude that science abstracts 
from particularity and individuality. If the moralist really were 
the logician he sometimes pretends to be, he would know that 
no general theory pretends to describe anything. The theory is 
just a symbolic notation. Scientific description is the use of this 
notation in the description of particular situations; and this 
necessarily involves the greatest deference to particular or indi- 
vidual character of which the human intellect at any time is 
capable. 

Science in its applications, as in its creation of knowledge, is 
intrinsically and immaculately moral — ^it is nothing else than 
the moral regard for individual being. Every sort of statement 
classifies individual things under general terras indicating com- 
mon properties; but it is only science which subjects general 
statement to particular verification and which expertly adapts 
it to the individual case. This is the very definition of science. 



TOE future of SCJENCR 581 

in their praiseworthy ciFort to emulate the theoretical achieve- 
ment of physical science, have retained some of the conceptual 
and mental habits of physical science. As the scientific study 
of human behavior perfects its theory, it will necessarily rid 
itself of concepts and habits ill-adapted to its specific material, 
which is living, intelligent, and individuated human beings. 
There, too, it will be seen that action directed by scientific 
knowledge is of necessity moral action, in this case controlled 
by respea for human character; and it will become a truism 
that an industry which injures or deceives human beings de- 
stroys the capital on which it lives. 

However, this mature and developed sociology does not yet 
erdst. What shall we do, in the meantime, to prevent the 
blind application of the physical and biological sciences to 
problems requiring a science of man which we do not yet 
possess? It is this unintelligent application of science, and this 
lack of social science, which support and even in some degree 
justify the attack upon science as a mechanistic and mateii^- 
tic faith destroying the human spirit. Turn from science to 
art or to religion, say these critics of science — ^there alone you 
will find a sort of knowledge which does justice to what is 
specific and individual in man. 

We must discern the clement of truth in this critidsm. It 
lies in its recognition of the specificity of nature. Knowledge 
of physical, vegetable, and animal process does not comprise 
a knowledge of what is specifically human. The difference be- 
tween man and other beings is more important, scientifically 
and morally, than his likeness to other things. We still suffer 
even in contemporary science from that seventeenth-century 
rationalism which identified reason with a single theory of 
reality, the error which empirical science in all of its develop- 
ment has steadily invalidated. It is that very rationalism which 
is mechanistic and materialistic. There is, says the rationalist, 
really but one universal Being, possessed everywhere of the 
character defined by self-evident principles of reason; and in- 



XHE FUTURE OF SCIENCE 


583 

specific differences which distingubh things, plants, animals, 
and men? Would not psychological theory and biological 
theory be special variations of that most abstract theory? 
Science would still be plural; psychophysics and biophysics 
would not be descriptive of geologic and astronomic fact. 

We may accredit to Samuel Alexander, Lloyd Morgan, and 
other “eincrgcTiiLsts” the discernment of this ineradicable 
pluralism of science. Theoretical analysis, say these men, has 
definite limits. The reduction of organic process to physico- 
chemical process (Le. the description of living behavior in 
physicochemical terms) docs not affect the reality of those 
specifically organic characters which distinguish organic from 
inorganic matter; and similarly the reduction of psychological 
fact to biological fact docs not erase the qualities distinguishing 
man from other animals. There is still required a plurality of 
distinct theories describing respectively physical, organic, and 
human structures. 

This is true; and so far as it goes we applaud the emergentist 
for his insight; but if wc stop with emergentism, we discredit 
science more profoundly, and undermine scientific faith more 
effectively, than docs any anti-intellectual critique of science. 
The emergentist still identifies science with its general theories, 
he is still a rationalist in his conception of truth. For he goes 
on to say that science and the human intellect are eternally 
limited to this analysis of fact into incommensurable sorts of 
fact, respectively physical, biological, and psychological or 
sociological. In virtue of our physical, biological, and psycho- 
logical theories we are enabled to discern in natural process 
some three variant structures, and so reach causal explanations 
of fact; but just for that reason, according to the emergentist, 
we must refrain from all effort to explain causally the relation 
of these differently structured processes, or their generation 
one from another. We may not seek to explain fully how 
metabolism transmits inorganic matter into vegetable and ani- 
mal flesh, nor how inorganic matter generated a living world. 



the future ok science 

The edmple truth is, we know, that the scientist must postu- 
late the presence of causal connection before he theorizes about 
it. The emergentist would require the scientist to have his 
theory perfected, even before he starts to construct theory or 
to entertain empirical hypothesis. The emergentist forbids all 
original speculation, all new hypothesis. This would fixate cur- 
rent theory, much as Greek mctaph5rsics made dogma of 
Greek science. But, to repeat, the source of his error is the fal- 
lacious notion of general or universal causation, exerted by 
general or universal Being. It is true that a primary postulate 
of science has been the universality of causal connection; but 
this postulate refers to particular causation, not to general or 
universal causation, of which science knows and will know 
nothing. The causal postulate is already affirmed in the truth 
which generates science, and which asserts that real being is 
individual being. “Real,” by definition, means causally effec- 
tive. The rationalistic error, we conclude, is to see in the ob- 
served similarity of particular causal processes a condition of 
the existence of such causal process. In truth, the similarity 
of causal processes is only the condition of our knowledge of 
specific causal process. We know that events are caused, 
whether or not we can describe their causes. We may not define 
nature in terms of the limitations of human knowledge. 

But what is the correction of the cmergentist’s error? Its full 
correction is philosophical truth, postulating the universality 
or ubiquity of necessary particular causation. Without this 
postulate all scientific inquiry stops, and scientific knowledge 
evaporates into mere verbiage. But its more pointed correction 
is a perception of the implications of this truth for current and 
future science. Science must and does postulate the complete 
and intelligible determinateness of the process of evolution; 
and as a matter of fact it already inquires, not without success, 
into the causal processes transmuting inorganic into organic 
matter. There is no reason why the evolutionary process should 
be cut for purposes of theoretical analysis at just two or three 



30 


THE FUTURE OF PHILOSOPHY 


T 

XN THE PREVIOUS CHAPTERS PHItOSOPHY HAS BEEN 

presented as a study politically motivated, inquiring 
into the implications of natural knowledge for the opposed 
postulates of necessity and freedom. The postulate of natural 
necessity has been shown to support the doctrine of absolutistic 
govermnent, and democratic self-government has been shown 
to require the postulate of natural freedom. Long controversy 
between rationalistic philosophers affirming necessity and em- 
pirical philosophers affirming freedom is closed by the victory 
of empirical pliilosophy, achieved in our own century. 

But now that the long controversy is over and the victory 
of liberal theory assured, it is necessary to turn back to do 
fuller justice to the rationalistic philosophers who defended 
the idea of natural necessity. What was the intention of these 
thinkers who so long and so fervently maintained their ration- 
alistic dogma? They were motivated by fear of social chaos, 
and by their desire for some absolute foundation for social in- 
stitutions. The authority of church or state, they felt, must be 
absolute. Sovereignty must be one and indivisible. Otherwise, 
they thought, there can be no authority, no sovereignty, no 
assurance of law and order. To this practical consideration was 
added the desire for some absolute foundation supporting 

587 



the future of philosophy ^89 

postulate of theoretical science. But science, we have seen, 
postulates also the particularity or difference of things, under- 
lying or accouipan)'ing their similarity. This is the meaning of 
die scientific emphasis upon particular fact as the criterion of 
general theory. Why, if things are radically different, should 
it be assumed that they will always present similarities? Why, 
if things arc free and not necessitated, should they necessarily 
present any universal structure? Why should the physied 
structure inferred from yesterday’s facts hold of tomorrow’s 
facts? Why should things conform at all? Why should nature 
not be chaos, devoid of large and lasting order? 

A possible reply to this question would be to say that nature 
may indeed be chaotic, and the apparent order of nature only 
a mental framework which we project into nature. This Kanr 
dan reply we cannot accept, because it destroys all scientific 
and moral faith. Another possible reply would be to say that 
sirce science docs exist, and supports itself upon the postulate 
of natural conformity, the existence of science establishes the 
fact that nature is uniform and must be uniform. This is to 
claim too much. Science discovers much uniformity in nature, 
it is true; but it discovers no reason why there must be uni- 
formity. In its acknowledgment of particular character as most 
real and ultimate, science implies that the order of nature rides 
upon a deeper disorder or chaos; and the physical scientist, in 
his recent researches, has demonstrated that this chaos or in- 
determinacy exists, and that it sets limits to scientific descrip- 
tion, Why should chaos not increase, and devour whatever of 
order there is? Human society occasionally falls prey to chaos. 
Why should nature at large not do so? "What keeps things 
similar, what makes them more similar than they were, or 
similar in new ways? 

The philosophy of the future will make its first principle the 
radical individuality of things; but it must also do justice to 
the uniformity of things which makes theoretical science pos- 
sible, and to the community of persons which makes govern- 



the FtmnuE of philosophy 


591 

consequence of this error was a failure to appreciate the effec- 
tive reality of individual character. The notion of fixed species, 
for example, requires the notion of a superindividual force 
'W’orking in or upon individuals, and confining their activities 
within specific limits. In fact, however, the species ejffects 
nothing — all that happens in this world is the result of indi- 
vidual interactions. Why a species or type persists is something 
that calls for explanation. It is not explained by the existence 
of the species. It is known that the continued existence of a 
species means that the species is adapted to its environment. 
What do we mean by “adaptation”? To say that a species is 
adapted means that the individuals comprising the species are 
adapted to one another and to the other things affecting them. 
Each individual thing exists in interaction with other inividual 
things. Each individual is dynamically dependent upon the 
other individuals to which it reacts. It is evident that the reac- 
tions of a thing may be destructive or preservative of the things 
which stimulate its reactions. If its reactions are predominantly 
destructive of these stimuli, the thing will no longer be stimu- 
lated, it will no longer react, it will cease to exist. 

In this way, we arc led back to the true insight which under- 
lay the Greek error. The Greeks saw that nature comprises an 
economy, composed of things so adapted to one another that 
their reactions to one another preserve them all. There is an 
economy of nature, even as ilcere is an economy of man. The 
Greek error was to suppose that this economic pattern is fixed, 
and that it preserves itself. In truth, the economic order is not 
fixed, it continually evolves; and it does not preserve itself, but 
it has been created, perpetuated, modified, and enlarged by the 
individuals dependent upon it for their existence. This is the 
true moral law of nature, embedded in the very conditions of 
individual existence; and out of this basic and original moral 
fact have proceeded, “in the order of time” as Anaximander 
said, all the orders and uniformities of the world. The individual 
entities composing nature are by definition different, and they 



the future of Pini-OSOPHY 


593 

exterminatory war. The same causes produce the same effects 
today. Out of this chaos of human violence, we must believe, 
arose the first political institution, possibly the clan system. 
The large and congested population was organized into a num- 
ber of clans. The individual identified himself only with his 
clan, which protected him from the mass-excitement and 
violence generated by the larger population. The individual 
could know his .small clan, and he could accept its rather rigid 
regulation of his behavior as a condition of peace. Among the 
clans was preserved a minimum of necessary intercourse, care- 
fully controlled. By the clan system an amorphous and 
delinquesccnt population was crystallized into a viable pat- 
tern. 

That political institutions originated somewhat in this way 
is suggested by the ritual and symbolism of the clans. Each 
clan identified itself with some plant or animal species; and the 
first “gods” appeared in mythical Wolves, Bulls, Oaks, and 
Fishes whose “life” was the enduring life of the clan. The 
clansmen were “children of the Bull”; and for them beef was 
tabu except when eaten ritually, with awe and trembling. What 
was the spell of these symbolisms, which have persisted through 
all the centuries of civilization down to today? Did the con- 
gested war-diseased population look back with nostalgia to the 
“state of nature,” which disappeared with the domestication of 
plant and animal food? Did men long to be again just an animal 
species sharing the natural economy of the wilderness? And 
did the clan system profess to be a return to that state of 
nature, in its solemn pretence that humans are “really” wolves, 
catde, sheep, and fish? Again and again, in later history, we see 
populations which have outgrown their political economic in- 
stitutions rise in social convulsion, and attempt a “return to 
nature.” How can man return to nature, what does the nos- 
talgia for nature mean? Man returns to nature only by his 
creation of political-economic institutions which remove con- 
gestion, and allow populations larger than have existed before 



THE FUTURE OF PHILOSOPHY 


595 

physicochemical environment, this advance being usually 
spoken of as “the scientific and industrial revolution.” For a 
century, there has been enormous human increase, leading to 
social congestion, mass-excitement, and exterminatory wars. 
Once again wc seek new political institutions, partitioning hu- 
manity into viable groups and regulating the intercourse of 
these groups. And once again men turn, in their search for a 
symbolism .supporting this new order, to a myth suggested by 
those interests which led to the congestion from which they 
must be saved. It was scientific interest in physicochemical 
nature which initiated the industrial revolution, with all of its 
social consequences. So there appears today the symbolism of 
materialistic philosophy, assuring us that if we will only believe 
that men are (not wolves or sheep or fish but) physicochemical 
mechanisms, the social future will be secure. This materialisdc 
philosophy is usually presented as nothing but science itself; 
but materialism is metaphysical myth, and not science. The 
physicochemical processes constituting the human being are 
to be understood more by way of their difference from other 
physicochemical processes than by their likeness to these. What- 
ever overlooks or denies specific or individual difference is a 
myth. Science is just the consistent refusal to neglect specific 
and individual differences. From science we deduce, in place 
of myth, the truth that respect for individual being is the 
foundation of all human and natural economy. 

When we survey the large course of evolution, we see that 
it has proceeded by great leaps or abrupt departures from type. 
This is what allows us to classify things into species, genera, 
orders, etc. Consider, for example, the chemical elements, each 
type of atom clearly demarcated from its ninety-odd fellows. 
Why is nature not qualitatively continuous, in such a way that 
between any two known types there will be found a third? 
Why is nature specific? The answer of science is that nontypi- 
cal individuals have existed, but have failed to survive and re- 
produce themselves. This still does not explain why ijew and 



597 


ihe future of philosophy 

congestion, in which things otherwise well adapted are over- 
somulatcd by things of their own kind. The individual is no 
longer adapted to members of its own species. There occurs in 
all of nature the violence and destruction which in human so- 
ciety is war or massacre; but there also may occur those crea- 
tive responses which initiate new sorts of adaptation supporting 
an increase of being. These creative responses are the reactions 
which have established new types and species, and advanced 
the progress of cosmic evolution. The whole course of evolu- 
tion may be understood as a creation of material nature, with 
continuous increase in the number or quantity of existent 
things, this increase requiring the continuous readaptation of 
things primarily to things of their ovra kind. Evolutionary 
progress is a qualitative progress, advanced by the rise of new 
and more deeply adapted types of being; but the qualitative 
progress is also a quantitative progress, the new type being 
“higher” just insofar as its reactions tolerate and support an 
increase of being. Thus the progress of human character is to 
be measured by the increase in human life which it makes 
possible; and human progress is accordingly most easily ap- 
preciated in terms of the development of the political economy, 
by means of which man has supported in health and secTOty 
a steadily increasing population. Materialism was right in its 
quantitative cuqihasls; but it overlooked the fact that the size 
and security of a population is! dependent upon the character 
of the individuals composing it. Idealism was right in its ein- 
phasis upon quality; but in rejecting quantitative naeasure, it 
deprived itself of all objective moral criteria, and inevitably 
became arbitrary and prejudiced. Use the quantative measure; 
but discover the quality which conditions the quantity of life 
or other existence! 

There is every reason to believe that human progress illus- 
trates the principle which has determined the evolution of 
nature at large. Human progress is conditioned by the ap- 
pearance and spread of new qualitative character , which sooner 



THE yUTURE OF PHILOSOPHY 


599 

of violent disturbance need not of itself effect the moderation 
of violence, by means of an advance to some new form of 
organization. This transcendence of old forms by new forms is 
unpredictable and mechanically inexplicable. How can it be . 
eixplained, if nor nicclianically? 

Mechanical explanation means the exhaustive analysis of any 
particular occurrence in tenns of unifonnities or similarities 
already known to invest entities of the sorts involved in the 
occurrence. But the appearance of a new type or species, estab- 
lishing a new pattern of interaction among things, by defini- 
tion escapes reduction to earlier uniformities. The new type is 
“emergent.” Darwin rightly attributed to chance the individual 
variations which he saw to be the condition of specific change. 
He did not mean, he said, that these variations are uncaused, 
but only that their causes escape detection.- Biological science 
through its genetic studies has advanced far beyond Darwin 
in its knowledge of the mechanisms of heredity; but it must 
still statistically attribute to “chance” the origin of what genetic 
combinations shall occur, to deteimine the character of a 
living population. Recourse to statistical methods involves a 
renunciation of strictly mechanical explanation. The latttar 
seeks to determine causal relations among individual entities, 
whereas statistical analysis seeks only to determine approximate 
uniformities of group behavior. 

It should not be supposed that the use of statistical methods 
prejudices the scientific conviction that everything happens by 
due cause. On the contrary, statistical science establishes this 
causal postulate more firmly. When the empirical philosopher 
challenges the postulate of universal necessity, he means to 
deny that particular events must necessarily conform to some 
universal design. He does not deny, rather he most emphati- 
cally insists, that particular events are causally necessitated by 
other particular events. His intention is to affirm particular 
causation, and to say that all effective causation is the work of 
individual entities interacting upon one another. This means. 



the future of philosophy 


6oi 

ways. The conformity of things, evolutionary science informs 
us, is more than bare uniformity. The conformities or uni- 
formities preserved by nature are ways of reciprocal adapta- 
tion among things, these reciprocities constituting a natural 
economy. The specific types of nature are due to the multipli- 
cation, spread, and persistence of certain individual characters 
which proved to be preeminently adapted. The classification 
of natural species points to a natural history, which, if we could 
know it, would inform us of the individual entities in which 
these species originatcil. There has been an historical succession 
of individual characters establishing new and better adapted 
types. These individuals have advanced natural evolution from 
its physical and chemical beginnings, through its mineral, or- 
ganic, and social stages, to what is supremely human in man 
today. These potent individuals are the true creators of the 
world. 

It is for the philosophy and science of the future to elaborate 
and propagate this truth. Only individuals are causally effective; 
and the total achievement of effective individuals is nothing 
less than the creation of the cosmos. It may some day be 
scientifically demonstrated that henceforth the hub of cosmic 
CTeation lies in the human life on this planet, in that the activi- 
ties of human life proceeding on earth exert just that small but 
decisive influence which makes the difference between cosmic 
health and cosmic decay. In this case, man would literally be- 
come the creator and providence of the world. However this 
may be, fact and logic compel the conclusion that nature is 
and always has been the creation of its individual constituents. 

It is a democratic world that we inhabit, the divine govern- 
ment of nature being wholly that of the things in it. 

This insight into the individual origins of natural uniformi- 
ties revolutionizes man’s concept of nature. It provides full and 
final release from the dogma of material necessity, and opens 
our eyes to the creative power which always has invested and 



the future of PUItOSOPHY (S03 

Human memory, in historical science, brmgs some acknowl- 
edgment to the seers, statesmen, scientists, and saints who by 
word and deed have established new adaptations of the human 
individual to his human and natural environment. Behind these 
heroes are the anonymous and unsung individuals who inspired 
them; and back of human history is the unrecorded past, hu- 
man and subhuman, no less rich in individual achievement 
which carried energy from its immaterial beginnings, through 
its chemical, mineral, and organic stages, to man and his 
civilization. 

We cannot develop this theme here. To do so would be to 
transform science into the religion it ought to be and some day 
will be. For what we shall learn is this: Creative love alone has 
from the beginning engineered this world; and if man abjures 
this religious love, the very stones will cry aloud their adora- 
tion, and take up the creative work which man lets fall. But 
we shall not let it fall. There lies ahead of man a heaven that 
shames all prophecy. That heaven, or annihilation, is his destiny. 

Philosophy in this way finally returns to the deeper truth 
of religion such as that of the New Testament, or of art when 
it points to a mercy and love which is the deeper fount of all 
justice. Political institutions, whatever their form, will not give 
us security and peace if they are observed only in the letter, 
and not in the kmdly spirit which created them and which they 
were created to serve. No more than logic provides scientific 
truth if it is not the instrument of willing attention to all par- 
ticular fact, does a democratic constitution secure justice if 
it is not used to implement a kindly and loving goodwill toward 
all human individuals. Let democratic society lose itt loving- 
kindness, let it confuse the machinery of democratic govern- 
ment with the tricks of power-politics, and very quickly a 
political majority will by harsh and autocratic action incite 
some offended minority to justified rebellion. The democratic 
constitution will secure justice if it makes effective in legisla- 



INDEX 


AB£IARD» l80 

Absolute, the, 409, 451, 461, 478 
absolute idealism, 417 
Absolute Mind, 368, 417 
absolutism, political, 5 If., 173 ff., 
197, 202 3ff., 208, 21 1, 214, 277, 
Ch. X7, 382, 408, 461, 566 
Academy of Plato, 81, 94, 100, 103 
Tactivisme, 443, 503 
adaptation, 489, 495, 591, 600 
Addresses to the German Nation, 
363 

AESCHYLXJS, 27 74, 2l8ff. 

aesthetic Knowledge, 89 ff., 288, 
354, 402, 44X jff. 
age of reason, 217, 225, 313 
agnosticism, 409 

ALBERT OF SAXONY, 225 
ALBERTOS MAGNUS (of Cologne), 
182 

ALEXANDER, 449, 473, 583 
Alexander of Macedon (the 
Great), ii8, 127 
Alfred, King of England, 142 
American government, 3 
American pragmatism, 490 
American revolution, 5, 486 

AMMONIUS SACCAS, I4I, l 6 l 

anal5mc geometry, 245 


analytic propositions, 337, 46S, 
513* 549 

ANAXAGORAS, 62 ff. 

ANAXIMANDER, 29, 33 ff., 48, 5 1, 62, 

74, 164, 591 

ANAXUVIENES, 33, 36 ff., 48, 5I ff. 
Angelic Doctor or Philosopher, 

the (ST. THOMAS AQUINAS), 182 
animal faith, 479 
ANSELM OF CANTERBURY, 1 79 

anthropomorphicism, 39 ff., 48, 52, 
258, 404 
Antichrist, 434 

anti-intellectuaiism, 326, 438 ff. 
antinomies of reason, 342 
ANTISTHENES, 1 26 
apathy, 128 
Apology, 75 

aposteriori knowledge, 336 
apriori knowledge, 336 
AQUINAS (ST. THOMAS), l8l ff., 476 
Arabic learning, 176, 182, 188 

ARISTARCHUS, 120, 221 
ARISTIPPUS, 133 

aristocracy, 117 

ARISTOTLE, 6, II, 3I, 37, 96, 102 ff., 
123, 140, 164, 171, 177, 182 ff., 
188, 221, 231, 236, 242, 362, 
412, 428, 476, 590 


605 



INDEX 

Comrmmst Manifesto, 39* 
“concrete logic,” 494, 551 
“conaetc universal,” 370 

CONDILLAC, 3*0 

Confessions of Aug;ustine, 163, 167 
Conscience (Kant), 349, 33* 
Consolations of Boethius, 14*, 177 
Constantine, the RiniH-ror, 175 
Constitution, 371 fF. 
constitutioraJ government, 20, 117, 
329 

constitutional land, 367 ff. 
contingency of nature, 183, 250, 
269, 299. 303 > J 33 f 4501 43 *> 
475 . 

continuity, 34, 203, 438 
contract theory, 135, 137, 204, 
207 ff., 3 II, 321 ff. 

Le Contrat Social, 321 
conventionalism, 32, 48, 67 S~, 78, 
95, i2d, 137, 443. 

COPERNICUS, Copemican revolu- 
tion, 221, 242, 464 
correspondence theory, 282 ff., 
488 

Comic Evolution, 480 
cosmology, 34, 37, 61 
creation, creationism, 15, 89 it., 91, 
163 ff., 248, 264, 601, 604 
Creative Evoltuion, 441 
criteria of truth, 191, 237, 282, 
415, 482, 502, 509, 543, Ch. 27 
critical philosophy, 13, 178, 277 ff-, 
313, Ch, j8, 342, 396, 438 ff., 
491 

critical realism, 281, 290 
Critique of Judpnent, 334, 353 
402 ff. 

Critique of Practical Reason, 334, 
348 ff., 357,400 

Critique of Eure Reason, 334 

35 i» 357 i 3 <Si 
Crito, 76 

CROCE, 444 ff . 


607 

Cynics, cynicism, iidff, 

Cyrenaics, 133 ff. 

Cyrus the Great, 22 

DARWIN, 51, 105, 373, 382, 392, 
410, 422, 428 ff„ 559, 599 
d’autricourt, 223 
Declaration of Independence, 5 
Deism, 319 ff. 
deity, 451 

definition, 72, 112, 114, 279, 282, 
46B 

DE LA METTRXE, 3 20 

demiurge, 91, 602 
democracy, 4 ff,, 20, 6z, 75, 77, 82, 
86, 117, 158, 174, 196, 207 ff., 
234, 318 ff., 324, 351, 397t 
434i 535 Ch. 28, 603 

DEMOCRITUS, 59 ff. 

De Rerum Nature, 137 
DESCARTES, 4, 12, I4, 2X6, 232, 
243 ff., 255 ff., 258, 263, 268, 
278, 283, 286, 304, 3X8, 331, 
334, 346, 348, 374, 406, 4X4, 

4*55 540* 547 
descriptive knowledge, 282 
determinism, 6x, 91, 165, 247, 260, 
301 ff., 3355 3^5 S., 447 » 
development, 105 ff. 

DEWEY, 491, 493 ff- ' 
dialectic, 95, 150, 362 ff. 
dialectical idciism, Ch. 19, 407, 
409 

dialectical materialism, 368, Ch. 20 
Dialogues Concerning N atural 
Religion, 308 
DIDEROT, 320 

DIOOENES, 127 

DIONYSIUS THE AREOPAGITE, 1 42, 

178 

discontinuity, 55, 263, 435* 43 ^ 
Discourse on Method, 244 
Discourses (of Rousseau), 324 
divine law, 53, 185 
divine right, 205 ff., 279 



INDEX 


609 


FRANCIS OF ASSISI, ST,, Franciscans, 
186 ff., X93ff., 223, 288, 312, 
418, 558 
Franco, 203 

freedom, 4, 7 ft, 125, 135, 163, 
x 66 y 198 ft, 204, 207 ft, 209, 
248, 252, 260, 265, 315, 324, 
390, 410, 470, 473, 524 ft 
Free Man^s Worship^ 158 
Freemasonry, 45 
FREGE, 467 

friendship, 90, 117, 136 
functional psychology, 488 
functional realism, 479 
Furies, the, 27, 52 

GALILEO, 12, 188, 216, 223 ft, 242, 
272 

Genealogy of Morals^ 434 
“general will,” 321ft, 388 
Geneva, 327 
Genghis Khan, 326 
genus, genera, 105ft 
geometry, 548 
German scholarship, 486 
Germany, 574 ff., 395. 437 

GIBBON, 152 
“golden mean,” ii 6 
“Good, the,” 103 
goodness, innate, 209 

GORGXAS, 69 

gravitation, 224, 243, 296, 386, 431, 
540 

Greek character, n, 20 ft, 143 ft, 
160 ft, 525 

Greek government, 20 ft 
Greek patriotism, 24 
Greek religion, 25 ft 
GREEN, T, IL, 416 ft 
GROSSETESTE, 188, I94, 2l6, 22 $ 

Ha 7 nlety 219, 356 

HARRINGTON, 382 

Harvard University, 478, 487 
HARVEY, 242 


heat, 35, 598 

hedonism, 133 ft., 309» 4* * 

HEGEL, 4, I4I, 329, 361, 363 ft., 
382, 387, 390, 403, 406 ft., 
412, 418, 437, 444, 449, 463, 
477> 493 ft-» 570 
Hellenic, Hellenistic, 124 
HELMHOLZ, 548 

H61oise, 1 81 

HELVETIUS, 319, 396 ff. 

Henry vii (Tudor), 173, 197, 219 
Henry viii (Tudor), 198, 382 

HESIOD, 32 

HERACLITUS, 49 ft., 59, 67 ft., 93, 95, 
370 

hierarchy of forms, io6, 266 
history, concept of, 4 ft, 15, 35, 
151, 165, 219, 320, 373, 378 ft., 
384 ft., 407, 425 ft., 440, 444, 
60 1 

historicity of Jesus, 156 
Hitler, 203 

HOBBES, 6 ft,, 203 ft., 207, 214, 
274 ft., 283, 287, 351, 406, 434 

HOLBACH, 320 

Holy Ghost, 162 
Homer, 32 
homo sapiens, 115 
human economy, 592 
humanism, 26, 89, 13 1, 157, Ch. 24 
human law, 53, 185 
HUME, 4, 8, 13, 64, 131, 241, 283, 
292, 294®., 317, 321, 33^ 
333 337> 348, 3701 4i4> 

416, 421, 427, 439, 448, 453, 
462, 468, 490, 506 ft., 535, 538 
HUSSERL, 476 ff. 

HUTTON, 429 

idea, 141 

idealism, 257, 264, 285, 291, Qi. 19* 
346, 365, 402, 416 ff., 420, 444, 
4<53. 495» 597 

Ideas of Reason, 339 ft., 346 
ideas, simple and complex, 280 



INDEX 


6ll 


290, 296, zgS, 509, 312, 317, 
35 3 < 57 » 370 » 382, 485. 490 
lodges, Pythagorean, 41 
logic, 43, 44, 56, 74, uiff., 1 3 1, 
179, 185, 235 fE., 242, 266 ff., 
344, 361, 367, 412, 465 ff., 471, 
494, 512, 517, 543, Ch. 27, 573, 

577 

LogiCf of Hegel, 369 
logical necessity, 268 
logical positivism, 512 ff. 
logical system, 512 
Logosy 140, 161, 521, 527 
LOTZE, 478 
Love and Strife, 62 
LucRETins, 137, 169, 177 
Lyceum, 124 
lyell, 429 

MACH, 478, 508 ff., 514, 517 
MACHIAVELLI, Il8, 169, 2Q3, 206 

majority rule, 322, 329 

MALEBRANCHE, 257 

Manichaeism, 162 
MARCUS AURELIUS, 12 J 
MARX, 4, 329, 361, 363, 368, 376, 
Ch. 20, 403 
^‘masses, the,” 412 
material cause, no 
Materialism, 59 ff., 109, 227 ff., 
273 ff., 287, 320, 368, 376, 388, 
404, 486, 595 

mathematics, 40 ff., 55, 59, 72, 94, 
97, 114, 126, 242, 244, 263, 
282, 305, 336, 398, 465 ff., 512, 

547 ^ ^ ^ 

matter, 91, 109 ff., 115, 246 ff., 205, 
363, 409 

Matter and Memory , 441 
mechanistic science, 35 ff., 51, 59» 
63, 165 ff., 247, 260, 320, 334, 
348, 356, 440 ff., 447 ff., 598 ff. 
medieval character, 172 ff., 217 
Meditations of Marcus Aurelius^ 
127 

MEINONG, 476 


Mentalism, 268, 346 
Messiah, 153 

method, 44, 56 ff., 71 ff., 78, 94 ff., 
97, 244, 415, 494, 578 
method of agreement, etc., 413 
method of reflection, 472 
Milesian philosophy, 30 ff., 45, 48, 
51, 59, 61 ff., 74, 92, 103 
MILL, JAMES, 410 
MILL, JOHN STUART, 4Ioff., 588 
mind, 288, 346, 368, 375, 376 
minority rights, 323, 41 1 
mixed state, n8 
modem character, n, 526 
modernism, 168, 176, 187, 1945., 
200, 221, 243 

modern science, ii, 182, 191 ff., 
Ch. 12, 415 
modes, 250 

Mohammedan World, 176, 182 
monad, monadism, 263 ff, 472 ff. 
monar^y, monarchism, 117, 147, 
202, 205 ff. 

monastic government, 41 
MONTAIGNE, 486 
MOORE, G. £., 462 
MORE, 382 

MORGAN, LLOYD, 583 

moral intuition (in Kant), 349 
moral law, 350, 5565. 
morphology of Aristotle, 114 
MOSES, 139, 188 
Moslem culture, 138, 182, 188 
motion, 50, 54, x88, 221, 246, 263 
music, 43, 354, 402 
Mussolini, 203, 329, 446, 563 
mutations, 108, 430, 436 
mystery religious, 41, 153 
mysticism, 138, 143, 187, 257, 262, 
289,418,561 

mythology, 32, 38, 404, 426, 593 ff. 
myths of Plato, 91, 99 

national church, 200 
nationalism, 169, 177, 218, 311, 
326 



INDEX 


physics of Aristode, 119 
physis, 4*5 
Pietism, 333 

MATO, n, 45. 57. <53 ff-. 09 ft*. 75. 
78, 80 102 ff., 108 If., 1 15 »•» 

121 if., i29ff.,i38ir-, i55.ftS3. 
188, 221, i27i ^3*1 ^33» ^3D» 
242, 247, 256, 269, 304, 34<5, 
362, 365, ^02, 425, 4^8, 437» 
468, 547’ 55^» 5^3^ 


590, 602 

PtoTiNUS, 14X ff.» 4^8, 442 
pluralism of specific forms, 100 
plurality of causes, 192 
plurality of sciences, 237 
POINCARE, 509 ff. 
political epoch, 3 
political pamphlets, 201 
political science, modem, 204 
Politics (of Aristode), iiyS, 
political realism, 8i, 82, 202, 375 
PORPHYRY, 141, 177. *79 
positivism, 344. 4 °°. 404 . 459 ft*. 

483,Ch.25.5>*ft*, „ 
postulates, philosophical, 8, 50, 02, 


340 

potentiality, 109 
pragmatics, 520 

pragmatism, 400, 403, 439* 459 » 
483, 485 ff., Ch. 244 517 _ 

Preamble to the Declaration of 
Independence^ 5 
predestination, 265 
preestablished harmony, 265 ff* 
Presbyterians, 198 ff. 
primary and secondary qualities, 
281, 282 ff., 289 
Prince, The, 203 
Principia Mathematica, 460 it., 
471 ff., 512 ff., 549 , , 

Principles of Human Knowledge, 


Principles of Psychology, 4^7 
process, 49 ff. 

“process of reality, 47^ 


progress, 3, 157, 217, 232, 389, 427, 
49«5» 597 ^ . 

progressive education, 327, 499 
proletariat, 388 

? rophecy, 28 
fotagoras, 10, 68 ff., 133 
Protestant ethics, 350 
protocol sentences, 518 
PROUDHON, 382 
PROUST, 441 

Prussia, 375 ^ ^ 

psychology of Plato, 84, 87 

PTOLEMY, 120 

“pure perception,” 441 
puritans, puritanism, 42, 198 ff., 
208, 252 ff., 259* 485 
purposiveness in nature, 350, 447 
PYTHAGORAS, Pythagoreans, 40 ff., 

4^1 54i 59» 9^» *®3» I35» 

221, 255, 33<^» ^ 7 ^^ 4 ^ 5 » 

469, 590 


Quakers, 333 

qualitative criterion of value, 597 
quantitative criterion of value, 597 
quintessence, 1154 *^9 


Rationalism, 44 » 55^*9 95 
224, 269, 304, Ch. i 3 » ^h. 144 
3i8,Ch, 18, Ch. 19 
rational intuition, 367, 386 
rational morality, 348 
realism, 179 ff*4 4 ^ 3 * ^3 


realistic logic, 517 
“Real appears, the,’ 370 
Realpolitik, 81, 82, 202 
“reconstruction of knowledge, 
338 ff., 398, 4 ^. 5 *® ^ 
reflection, method of, 3^4 
Reformation, 149* i 7 ^i ’ 


regulative principles, 343 

relativism, 5^4 ^ 7 > 

relativity of form and matter, 120 



p)EX 

|#bstance, 31, 49 fF,, 64, 66, no, 
r 281,300,339 
iiiberman, 433 S* 

S ireme Court, 571 ff, 
ogism, xiz 
nbolic systems, 267 
npathy, 3x0 
nposiWHy 402 
ntax, 519 

tithctic propositions, 469 
Tracuse, 86 

Sutological sentences, 512 
technocracy, 408 
|^olog7, 165, 356 ff., 447 
A.LES, 2Z, 31, 33 ff., 48, J4<S 
fcodicy, 130, 268 
‘ eology, 308 
Uorei^ 42 

‘ bory, theoretical form, 45, 57, 
72, 88, 97 ff., 384 ff., 484 
ficory of ideas,” 8 
eory of the state, 213, 328, 
, 375 

liomism, 182 ff. 
aoRBAU, 126 , 486 
ree potencies of man, 1x5 
ree stages of history, 388, 404, 
407 

ree states of being, 42, 53, 82 
feucYDiDES, 426 
film Spoke ZaratbustrUy 434 
\imaeuSy 91, 177, 602 
" ne, 51, 2(57, 338i 399. 439. 445 ff-. 

450. 480 
(>i.sToi, 220 

Xractatus Philosophicus, 517 
mscendental dialectic, 361 
iscendentalism, 44, 53, 55, 63, 
Ij, 74. 77. 81, 91. 9 <S. “ 9 ff-. * 4 *. 
437. 4<Si. 486 

nscendental Ego, 363 
tansmutation, 36 
\'reati$e on Human Namrcy 295, 
4x6 


615 

Trinity y 161, 180 
truth, philosophical, 144, 404, 543, 
Ch. 27, 562 

Tudor dynasty, 173, 197 ff., 382 
Two Sources of Religion and 
Morality y 443 
tyranny, 527, 568 

uniformity of nature, iiff., 413, 
588, 600 

**unity of science,” 515 
universals, universi being, 5, 
. 178 ff., 1924 227, 433, 557 
utilitarianism, 68, 3x0, 396, 410 
utility, 310 
Utopia, 82, 382 

verification theory, 501 
Vienna Circle, 517 
Views on Representative Oovem-- 
menty 4x0 

virtue, 72®., 128, 135, 155 ff., 357 
vitalism, 121, 429 
VOLTAIRE, 320, 329 

Wars of the Roses, 173, 219 
water, 33, 598 

Way of Truthy Way of Opinion, 
54 

Whigs, 206 ff., 4x1 

WHITEHEAD, 466 ff., 47I ff., 549 
WHITZVCAN, 486 
Will to Belkvey 4^2 
Will to Powery 434 
will to truth, 555 

WITTGENSTEIN, 5x7 
Wissenschaftslehrey 363 
World as Will md as Idea, 399 
world-soul, X42 

XENOPHON, 71, 78 


ZENO, 127